SlideShare uma empresa Scribd logo
1 de 64
Aristotle (Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης Aristotélēs) (384 BC – 322 BC) was a Greek philosopher, a 
student of Plato and teacher of Alexander the Great. He wrote on many subjects, including 
physics, metaphysics, poetry, theater, music, logic, rhetoric, politics, government, ethics, biology 
and zoology. 
Together with Plato and Socrates (Plato's teacher), Aristotle is one of the most important 
founding figures in Western philosophy. He was the first to create a comprehensive system of 
Western philosophy, encompassing morality and aesthetics, logic and science, politics and 
metaphysics. Aristotle's views on the physical sciences profoundly shaped medieval scholarship, 
and their influence extended well into the Renaissance, although they were ultimately replaced 
by modern physics. In the biological sciences, some of his observations were only confirmed to 
be accurate in the nineteenth century. His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, 
which were incorporated in the late nineteenth century into modern formal logic. In metaphysics, 
Aristotelianism had a profound influence on philosophical and theological thinking in the Islamic 
and Jewish traditions in the Middle Ages, and it continues to influence Christian theology, 
especially Eastern Orthodox theology, and the scholastic tradition of the Roman Catholic 
Church. All aspects of Aristotle's philosophy continue to be the object of active academic study 
today. 
Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues (Cicero described his literary style 
as "a river of gold"), it is thought that the majority of his writings are now lost and only about 
one third of the original works have survived.[1] 
Contents 
[hide] 
· 1 Life 
· 2 Logic 
o 2.1 History 
o 2.2 Analytics and the Organon 
· 3 Aristotle's scientific method 
· 4 Physics 
o 4.1 The five elements 
o 4.2 Causality, The Four Causes 
o 4.3 Chance and spontaneity 
· 5 Metaphysics 
o 5.1 Substance, potentiality and actuality 
o 5.2 Universals and particulars 
· 6 Biology and medicine 
o 6.1 Empirical research program 
o 6.2 Classification of living things 
o 6.3 Theory of biological forms and souls 
o 6.4 Aristotle's successor: Theophrastus 
o 6.5 Influence on Hellenistic medicine 
· 7 Practical Philosophy 
o 7.1 Ethics
o 7.2 Politics 
o 7.3 Rhetoric and poetics 
· 8 The loss of his works 
· 9 Legacy 
· 10 List of Aristotle's works 
· 11 Notes and References 
· 12 Further reading 
· 13 See also 
· 14 External links 
o 14.1 Collections of Aristotle's works 
o 14.2 Articles on Aristotle 
Life 
Aristotle was born in Stageira, Chalcidice, in 384 BC, about 55 km east of modern-day 
Thessaloniki.[2] His father, Nicomachus was the personal physician to King Amyntas of 
Macedon. Aristotle was trained and educated as a member of the aristocracy. At about the age of 
eighteen, he went to Athens to continue his education at Plato's Academy. Aristotle remained at 
the academy for nearly twenty years, not leaving until after Plato's death in 347 BC. He then 
traveled with Xenocrates to the court of his friend Hermias of Atarneus in Asia Minor. While in 
Asia, Aristotle traveled with Theophrastus to the island of Lesbos, where together they 
researched the botany and zoology of the island. Aristotle married Hermias's adoptive daughter 
(or niece) Pythias. She bore him a daughter, whom they named Pythias. Soon after Hermias' 
death, Aristotle was invited by Philip of Macedon to become tutor to Alexander the Great in 343 
B.C.[3] 
During his time as the head of Macedon's royal academy, Aristotle gave lessons not only to 
Alexander, but also to two other future kings: Ptolemy and Cassander. In his Politics, Aristotle 
states that only one thing could justify monarchy, and that was if the virtue of the king and his 
family were greater than the virtue of the rest of the citizens put together. Tactfully, he included 
the young prince and his father in that category. Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern 
conquest, and his attitude towards Persia was unabashedly ethnocentric. In one famous example, 
he counsels Alexander to be 'a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians, to look after 
the former as after friends and relatives, and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants'.[4] 
Near the end of Alexander's life he began to suspect plots, and threatened Aristotle in letters. 
Aristotle had made no secret of his contempt for Alexander's pretense of divinity, and the king 
had executed Aristotle's grand-nephew Callisthenes as a traitor. A widespread tradition in 
antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in Alexander's death, but there is little evidence for 
this.[5] 
By 335 BC he had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the Lyceum. 
Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years. While in Athens, his wife 
Pythias died, and Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stageira, who bore him a son
whom he named after his father, Nicomachus. According to the Suda, he also had an eromenos, 
Palaephatus of Abydus.[6] 
It is during this period in Athens from 335 B.C. to 323 B.C. when Aristotle is believed to have 
composed many of his works.[7] Aristotle wrote many dialogues, only fragments of which 
survived. The works that have survived are in treatise form and were not, for the most part, 
intended for widespread publication, as they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his 
students. His most important treatises include Physics, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics, 
Politics, De Anima (On the Soul) and Poetics. 
Aristotle not only studied almost every subject possible at the time, but made significant 
contributions to most of them. In physical science, Aristotle studied anatomy, astronomy, 
economics, embryology, geography, geology, meteorology, physics and zoology. In philosophy, 
he wrote on aesthetics, ethics, government, metaphysics, politics, psychology, rhetoric and 
theology. He also studied education, foreign customs, literature and poetry. His combined works 
constitute a virtual encyclopedia of Greek knowledge. It has been suggested that Aristotle was 
probably the last person to know everything there was to be known in his own time.[8] 
Upon Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens once again flared. Eurymedon the 
hierophant denounced Aristotle for not holding the gods in honor. Aristotle fled the city to his 
mother's family estate in Chalcis, explaining, "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against 
philosophy,"[9] a reference to Athens's prior trial and execution of Socrates. However, he died in 
Euboea of natural causes within the year (in 322 BC). Aristotle named chief executor his student 
Antipater and left a will in which he asked to be buried next to his wife.[10] 
Logic 
Main article: Term logic 
For more details on this topic, see Non-Aristotelian logic. 
Aristotle's conception of logic was the dominant form of logic until 19th century advances in 
mathematical logic. Kant stated in the Critique of Pure Reason that Aristotle's theory of logic 
completely accounted for the core of deductive inference. 
History 
Aristotle "says that 'on the subject of reasoning' he 'had nothing else on an earlier date to speak 
of'".[11] However, Plato reports that syntax was devised before him, by Prodicus of Ceos, who 
was concerned by the correct use of words. Logic seems to have emerged from dialectics; the 
earlier philosophers made frequent use of concepts like reductio ad absurdum in their 
discussions, but never truly understood the logical implications. Even Plato had difficulties with 
logic; although he had a reasonable conception of a deduction system, he could never actually 
construct one and relied instead on his dialectic.[12] Plato believed that deduction would simply 
follow from premises, hence he focused on maintaining solid premises so that the conclusion 
would logically follow. Consequently, Plato realized that a method for obtaining conclusions
would be most beneficial. He never succeeded in devising such a method, but his best attempt 
was published in his book Sophist, where he introduced his division method.[13] 
Analytics and the Organon 
Main article: Organon 
What we today call Aristotelian logic, Aristotle himself would have labeled "analytics". The term 
"logic" he reserved to mean dialectics. Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original 
form, since it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. The logical works of 
Aristotle were compiled into six books in about the early 1st century AD: 
1. Categories 
2. On Interpretation 
3. Prior Analytics 
4. Posterior Analytics 
5. Topics 
6. On Sophistical Refutations 
The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this 
list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of 
simple terms in the Categories, to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the 
Analytics) and dialectics (in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations). There is one volume of 
Aristotle's concerning logic not found in the Organon, namely the fourth book of Metaphysics.. 
[12] 
Aristotle's scientific method 
Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of The School of Athens, a fresco by Raphael. Aristotle 
gestures to the earth, representing his belief in knowledge through empirical observation and 
experience, while holding a copy of his Nicomachean Ethics in his hand, whilst Plato gestures to 
the heavens, representing his belief in The Forms. 
For more details on this topic, see Aristotle's theory of universals.
Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the universal. Aristotle, however, found the 
universal in particular things, which he called the essence of things, while Plato finds that the 
universal exists apart from particular things, and is related to them as their prototype or 
exemplar. For Aristotle, therefore, philosophic method implies the ascent from the study of 
particular phenomena to the knowledge of essences, while for Plato philosophic method means 
the descent from a knowledge of universal Forms (or ideas) to a contemplation of particular 
imitations of these. For Aristotle, "form" still refers to the unconditional basis of phenomena but 
is "instantiated" in a particular substance (see Universals and particulars, below). In a certain 
sense, Aristotle's method is both inductive and deductive, while Plato's is essentially deductive 
from a priori principles.[14] 
In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the 
phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, 
biology and other natural sciences. In modern times, the scope of philosophy has become limited 
to more generic or abstract inquiries, such as ethics and metaphysics, in which logic plays a 
major role. Today's philosophy tends to exclude empirical study of the natural world by means of 
the scientific method. In contrast, Aristotle's philosophical endeavors encompassed virtually all 
facets of intellectual inquiry. 
In the larger sense of the word, Aristotle makes philosophy coextensive with reasoning, which he 
also would describe as "science". Note, however, that his use of the term science carries a 
different meaning than that covered by the term "scientific method". For Aristotle, "all science 
(dianoia) is either practical, poetical or theoretical" (Metaphysics 1025b25). By practical science, 
he means ethics and politics; by poetical science, he means the study of poetry and the other fine 
arts; by theoretical science, he means physics, mathematics and metaphysics. 
If logic (or "analytics") is regarded as a study preliminary to philosophy, the divisions of 
Aristotelian philosophy would consist of: (1) Logic; (2) Theoretical Philosophy, including 
Metaphysics, Physics, Mathematics, (3) Practical Philosophy and (4) Poetical Philosophy. 
In the period between his two stays in Athens, between his times at the Academy and the 
Lyceum, Aristotle conducted most of the scientific thinking and research for which he is 
renowned today. In fact, most of Aristotle's life was devoted to the study of the objects of natural 
science. Aristotle's metaphysics contains observations on the nature of numbers but he made no 
original contributions to mathematics. He did, however, perform original research in the natural 
sciences, e.g., botany, zoology, physics, astronomy, chemistry, meteorology, and several other 
sciences. 
Aristotle's writings on science are largely qualitative, as opposed to quantitative. Beginning in 
the sixteenth century, scientists began applying mathematics to the physical sciences, and 
Aristotle's work in this area was deemed hopelessly inadequate. His failings were largely due to 
the absence of concepts like mass, velocity, force and temperature. He had a conception of speed 
and temperature, but no quantitative understanding of them, which was partly due to the absence 
of basic experimental devices, like clocks and thermometers.
A green and red Perseid meteor is striking the sky just below the Milky Way in August 2007. 
His writings provide an account of many scientific observations, a mixture of precocious 
accuracy and curious errors. For example, in his History of Animals he claimed that human males 
have more teeth than females.[15] In a similar vein, John Philoponus, and later Galileo, showed by 
simple experiments that Aristotle's theory that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is 
incorrect.[16] On the other hand, Aristotle refuted Democritus's claim that the Milky Way was 
made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out 
(correctly, even if such reasoning was bound to be dismissed for a long time) that, given "current 
astronomical demonstrations" that "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the 
distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then...the sun shines 
on all the stars and the earth screens none of them."[17] 
In places, Aristotle goes too far in deriving 'laws of the universe' from simple observation and 
over-stretched reason. Today's scientific method assumes that such thinking without sufficient 
facts is ineffective, and that discerning the validity of one's hypothesis requires far more rigorous 
experimentation than that which Aristotle used to support his laws. 
Aristotle also had some scientific blind spots. He posited a geocentric cosmology that we may 
discern in selections of the Metaphysics, which was widely accepted up until the 1500s. From the 
3rd century to the 1500s, the dominant view held that the Earth was the center of the universe 
(geocentrism). 
Since he was perhaps the philosopher most respected by European thinkers during and after the 
Renaissance, these thinkers often took Aristotle's erroneous positions as given, which held back 
science in this epoch.[18] However, Aristotle's scientific shortcomings should not mislead one into 
forgetting his great advances in the many scientific fields. For instance, he founded logic as a 
formal science and created foundations to biology that were not superseded for two millennia. 
Moreover, he introduced the fundamental notion that nature is composed of things that change 
and that studying such changes can provide useful knowledge of underlying constants. 
Physics 
Main article: Physics (Aristotle) 
The five elements
Main article: Classical element 
· Fire , which is hot and dry. 
· Earth , which is cold and dry. 
· Air , which is hot and wet. 
· Water , which is cold and wet. 
· Aether , which is the divine substance that makes up the heavenly spheres and heavenly 
bodies (stars and planets). 
Each of the four earthly elements has its natural place; the earth at the centre of the universe, 
then water, then air, then fire. When they are out of their natural place they have natural motion, 
requiring no external cause, which is towards that place; so bodies sink in water, air bubbles up, 
rain falls, flame rises in air. The heavenly element has perpetual circular motion. 
Causality, The Four Causes 
Main article: Four causes 
· The material cause is that from which a thing comes into existence as from its part, 
constituents, substratum or materials. This reduces the explanation of causes to the parts 
(factors, elements, constituents, ingredients) forming the whole (system, structure, 
compound, complex, composite, or combination), a relationship known as the part-whole 
causation. Simply put it is the influence of the material substances on the event. So 
imagine two dominos, the first of which is lighter. The first is knocked over into the 
second but does not have enough power to knock it over, this is Material cause. 
· The formal cause tells us what a thing is, that any thing is determined by the definition, 
form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis or archetype. It embraces the account of causes 
in terms of fundamental principles or general laws, as the whole (i.e., macrostructure) is 
the cause of its parts, a relationship known as the whole-part causation. Plainly put it is 
the influence of the form (essence) of the things on the event. So take the two dominos 
again except this time the second is shaped to prevent it from falling *eg. triangular.* this 
is formal cause. 
· The efficient cause is that from which the change or the ending of the change first starts. 
It identifies 'what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is changed' and 
so suggests all sorts of agents, nonliving or living, acting as the sources of change or 
movement or rest. Representing the current understanding of causality as the relation of 
cause and effect, this covers the modern definitions of "cause" as either the agent or 
agency or particular events or states of affairs. More simply again that which immediately 
sets the thing in motion. So take the two dominos this time of equal weighting, the first is 
knocked over causing the second also to fall over. This is effectively efficient cause. 
· The final cause is that for the sake of which a thing exists or is done, including both 
purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. The final cause or telos is the purpose 
or end that something is supposed to serve, or it is that from which and that to which the 
change is. This also covers modern ideas of mental causation involving such 
psychological causes as volition, need, motivation, or motives, rational, irrational, ethical, 
all that gives purpose to behavior.
Additionally, things can be causes of one another, causing each other reciprocally, as hard work 
causes fitness and vice versa, although not in the same way or function, the one is as the 
beginning of change, the other as the goal. (Thus Aristotle first suggested a reciprocal or circular 
causality as a relation of mutual dependence or influence of cause upon effect). Moreover, 
Aristotle indicated that the same thing can be the cause of contrary effects; its presence and 
absence may result in different outcomes. Simply it is the goal or purpose that brings about an 
event (not necessarily a mental goal). Taking our two dominos, it requires someone to 
intentionally knock the dominos over as they cannot fall themselves. 
Aristotle marked two modes of causation: proper (prior) causation and accidental (chance) 
causation. All causes, proper and incidental, can be spoken as potential or as actual, particular or 
generic. The same language refers to the effects of causes, so that generic effects assigned to 
generic causes, particular effects to particular causes, operating causes to actual effects. 
Essentially, causality does not suggest a temporal relation between the cause and the effect. 
All further investigations of causality will consist of imposing the favorite hierarchies on the 
order causes, such as final > efficient > material > formal (Thomas Aquinas), or of restricting all 
causality to the material and efficient causes or to the efficient causality (deterministic or chance) 
or just to regular sequences and correlations of natural phenomena (the natural sciences 
describing how things happen instead of explaining the whys and wherefores). 
Chance and spontaneity 
Spontaneity and chance are causes of effects. Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of 
accidental things. It is "from what is spontaneous" (but note that what is spontaneous does not 
come from chance). For a better understanding of Aristotle's conception of "chance" it might be 
better to think of "coincidence": Something takes place by chance if a person sets out with the 
intent of having one thing take place, but with the result of another thing (not intended) taking 
place. For example: A person seeks donations. That person may find another person willing to 
donate a substantial sum. However, if the person seeking the donations met the person donating, 
not for the purpose of collecting donations, but for some other purpose, Aristotle would call the 
collecting of the donation by that particular donator a result of chance. It must be unusual that 
something happens by chance. In other words, if something happens all or most of the time, we 
cannot say that it is by chance. 
There is also more specific kind of chance, which Aristotle names "luck", that can only apply to 
human beings, since it is in the sphere of moral actions. According to Aristotle, luck must 
involve choice (and thus deliberation), and only humans are capable of deliberation and choice. 
"What is not capable of action cannot do anything by chance".[19] 
Metaphysics 
Main article: Metaphysics (Aristotle)
Aristotle defines metaphysics as "the knowledge of immaterial being," or of "being in the highest 
degree of abstraction." He refers to metaphysics as "first philosophy", as well as "the theologic 
science." 
Substance, potentiality and actuality 
Aristotle examines the concept of substance and essence (ousia) in his Metaphysics, Book VII 
and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form. As he 
proceeds to the book VIII, he concludes that the matter of the substance is the substratum or the 
stuff of which it is composed, e.g. the matter of the house are the bricks, stones, timbers etc., or 
whatever constitutes the potential house. While the form of the substance, is the actual house, 
namely 'covering for bodies and chattels' or any other differentia (see also predicables). The 
formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the 
differentia is the account of the form.[20] 
With regard to the change (kinesis) and its causes now, as he defines in his Physics and On 
Generation and Corruption 319b-320a, he distinguishes the coming to be from: 1) growth and 
diminution, which is change in quantity; 2) locomotion, which is change in space; and 3) 
alteration, which is change in quality. 
The coming to be is a change where nothing persists of which the resultant is a property. In that 
particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (dynamis) and actuality (entelecheia) 
in association with the matter and the form. 
Referring to potentiality, this is what a thing is capable of doing, or being acted upon, if it is not 
prevented by something else. For example, the seed of a plant in the soil is potentially (dynamei) 
plant, and if is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially beings can either 
'act' (poiein) or 'be acted upon' (paschein), which can be either innate or learned. For example, 
the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate - being acted upon), while the capability of 
playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise - acting). 
Actuality is the fulfillment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (telos) is the principle 
of every change, and for the sake of the end exists potentiality, therefore actuality is the end. 
Referring then to our previous example, we could say that actuality is when the seed of the plant 
becomes a plant. 
" For that for the sake of which a thing is, is its principle, and the becoming is for the sake of the 
end; and the actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this that the potentiality is acquired. For 
animals do not see in order that they may have sight, but they have sight that they may see."[21] 
In conclusion, the matter of the house is its potentiality and the form is its actuality. The formal 
cause (aitia) then of that change from potential to actual house, is the reason (logos) of the house 
builder and the final cause is the end, namely the house itself. Then Aristotle proceeds and 
concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality.
With this definition of the particular substance (i.e., matter and form), Aristotle tries to solve the 
problem of the unity of the beings, e.g., what is that makes the man one? Since, according to 
Plato there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to 
Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same thing.[22] 
Universals and particulars 
Main article: Aristotle's theory of universals 
Aristotle's predecessor, Plato, argued that all things have a universal form, which could be either 
a property, or a relation to other things. When we look at an apple, for example, we see an apple, 
and we can also analyze a form of an apple. In this distinction, there is a particular apple and a 
universal form of an apple. Moreover, we can place an apple next to a book, so that we can speak 
of both the book and apple as being next to each other. 
Plato argued that there are some universal forms that are not a part of particular things. For 
example, it is possible that there is no particular good in existence, but "good" is still a proper 
universal form. Bertrand Russell is a contemporary philosopher that agreed with Plato on the 
existence of "uninstantiated universals". 
Aristotle disagreed with Plato on this point, arguing that all universals are instantiated. Aristotle 
argued that there are no universals that are unattached to existing things. According to Aristotle, 
if a universal exists, either as a particular or a relation, then there must have been, must be 
currently, or must be in the future, something on which the universal can be predicated. 
Consequently, according to Aristotle, if it is not the case that some universal can be predicated to 
an object that exists at some period of time, then it does not exist. 
One way for contemporary philosophers to justify this position is by asserting the eleatic 
principle. 
In addition, Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals. As Plato spoke of the 
world of the forms, a location where all universal forms subsist, Aristotle maintained that 
universals exist within each thing on which each universal is predicated. So, according to 
Aristotle, the form of apple exists within each apple, rather than in the world of the forms. 
Biology and medicine 
In Aristotelian science, most especially in biology, things he saw himself have stood the test of 
time better than his retelling of the reports of others, which contain error and superstition. He 
dissected animals, but not humans and his ideas on how the human body works have been almost 
entirely superseded. 
Empirical research program
Octopus swimming 
Torpedo fuscomaculata 
Aristotle is the earliest natural historian whose work has survived in some detail. Aristotle 
certainly did research on the natural history of Lesbos, and the surrounding seas and 
neighbouring areas. The works that reflect this research, such as History of Animals, Generation 
of Animals, and Parts of Animals, contain some observations and interpretations, along with 
sundry myths and mistakes. The most striking passages are about the sea-life visible from 
observation on Lesbos and available from the catches of fishermen. His observations on catfish, 
electric fish (Torpedo) and angler-fish are detailed, as is his writing on cephalopods, namely, 
Octopus, Sepia (cuttlefish) and the paper nautilus (Argonauta argo). His description of the 
hectocotyl arm was about two thousand years ahead of its time, and widely disbelieved until its 
rediscovery in the nineteenth century. He separated the aquatic mammals from fish, and knew 
that sharks and rays were part of the group he called Selachē (selachians).[23] 
Leopard shark 
Another good example of his methods comes from the Generation of Animals in which Aristotle 
describes breaking open fertilized chicken eggs at intervals to observe when visible organs were 
generated. 
He gave accurate descriptions of ruminants' four-chambered fore-stomachs, and of the 
ovoviviparous embryological development of the hound shark Mustelus mustelus.[24] 
Classification of living things
Aristotle's classification of living things contains some elements which still existed in the 
nineteenth century. What the modern zoologist would call vertebrates and invertebrates, Aristotle 
called 'animals with blood' and 'animals without blood' (he was not to know that complex 
invertebrates do make use of haemoglobin, but of a different kind from vertebrates). Animals 
with blood were divided into live-bearing (humans and mammals), and egg-bearing (birds and 
fish). Invertebrates ('animals without blood') are insects, crustacea (divided into non-shelled – 
cephalopods – and shelled) and testacea (molluscs). In some respects, this incomplete 
classification is better than that of Linnaeus, who crowded the invertebrata together into two 
groups, Insecta and Vermes (worms). 
For Charles Singer, "Nothing is more remarkable than [Aristotle's] efforts to [exhibit] the 
relationships of living things as a scala naturae"[23] Aristotle's History of Animals classified 
organisms in relation to a hierarchical "Ladder of Life" (scala naturae), placing them according 
to complexity of structure and function so that higher organisms showed greater vitality and 
ability to move.[25] 
Aristotle believed that intellectual purposes, i.e., formal causes, guided all natural processes. 
Such a teleological view gave Aristotle cause to justify his observed data as an expression of 
formal design. Noting that "no animal has, at the same time, both tusks and horns," and "a single-hooved 
animal with two horns I have never seen," Aristotle suggested that Nature, giving no 
animal both horns and tusks, was staving off vanity, and giving creatures faculties only to such a 
degree as they are necessary. Noting that ruminants had a multiple stomachs and weak teeth, he 
supposed the first was to compensate for the latter, with Nature trying to preserve a type of 
balance.[26] 
In a similar fashion, Aristotle believed that creatures were arranged in a graded scale of 
perfection rising from plants on up to man, the scala naturae or Great Chain of Being.[27] His 
system had eleven grades, arranged according "to the degree to which they are infected with 
potentiality", expressed in their form at birth. The highest animals laid warm and wet creatures 
alive, the lowest bore theirs cold, dry, and in thick eggs. 
Theory of biological forms and souls 
Aristotle also held that the level of a creature's perfection was reflected in its form, but not 
preordained by that form. Ideas like this, and his ideas about souls, are not regarded as science at 
all in modern times. 
He placed emphasis on the type(s) of soul an organism possessed, asserting that plants possess a 
vegetative soul, responsible for reproduction and growth, animals a vegetative and a sensitive 
soul, responsible for mobility and sensation, and humans a vegetative, a sensitive, and a rational 
soul, capable of thought and reflection.[28] 
Aristotle, in contrast to earlier philosophers, but in accordance with the Egyptians, placed the 
rational soul in the heart, rather than the brain.[29] Notable is Aristotle's division of sensation and 
thought, which generally went against previous philosophers, with the exception of Alcmaeon.[30]
His analysis of procreation is frequently criticized on the grounds that it presupposes an active, 
ensouling masculine element bringing life to an inert, passive, lumpen female element; it is on 
these grounds that Aristotle is considered by some feminist critics to have been a misogynist.[31] 
Aristotle's successor: Theophrastus 
Frontispiece to a 1644 version of the expanded and illustrated edition of Historia Plantarum (ca. 
1200), which was originally written around 200 BC 
Main articles: Theophrastus and Historia Plantarum 
Aristotle's successor at the Lyceum, Theophrastus, wrote a series of books on botany—the 
History of Plants—which survived as the most important contribution of antiquity to botany, 
even into the Middle Ages. Many of Theophrastus' names survive into modern times, such as 
carpos for fruit, and pericarpion for seed vessel. 
Rather than focus on formal causes, as Aristotle did, Theophrastus suggested a mechanistic 
scheme, drawing analogies between natural and artificial processes, and relying on Aristotle's 
concept of the efficient cause. Theophrastus also recognized the role of sex in the reproduction of 
some higher plants, though this last discovery was lost in later ages.[32] 
Influence on Hellenistic medicine 
For more details on this topic, see Medicine in ancient Greece. 
After Theophrastus, the Lyceum failed to produce any original work. Though interest in 
Aristotle's ideas survived, they were generally taken unquestioningly.[33] It is not until the age of 
Alexandria under the Ptolemies that advances in biology can be again found. 
The first medical teacher at Alexandria Herophilus of Chalcedon, corrected Aristotle, placing 
intelligence in the brain, and connected the nervous system to motion and sensation. Herophilus 
also distinguished between veins and arteries, noting that the latter pulse while the former do not. 
[34] Though a few ancient atomists such as Lucretius challenged the teleological viewpoint of 
Aristotelian ideas about life, teleology (and after the rise of Christianity, natural theology) would 
remain central to biological thought essentially until the 18th and 19th centuries. Ernst Mayr
claimed that there was "nothing of any real consequence in biology after Lucretius and Galen 
until the Renaissance."[35] Aristotle's ideas of natural history and medicine survived, but they 
were generally taken unquestioningly.[36] 
Practical Philosophy 
Ethics 
Main article: Aristotelian ethics 
Aristotle considered ethics to be a practical science, i.e., one mastered by doing rather than 
merely reasoning. Further, Aristotle believed that ethical knowledge is not certain knowledge 
(such as metaphysics or epistemology) but is general knowledge. He wrote several treatises on 
ethics, including most notably, Nichomachean Ethics, in which he outlines what is commonly 
called virtue ethics. 
Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function of a thing. An eye is only a good 
eye in so much as it can see, because the proper function of an eye is sight. Aristotle reasoned 
that man must have a function uncommon to anything else, and that this function must be an 
activity of the soul. Aristotle identified the best activity of the soul as eudaimonia: a happiness or 
joy that pervades the good life. Aristotle taught that to achieve the good life, one must live a 
balanced life and avoid excess. This balance, he taught, varies among different persons and 
situations, and exists as a golden mean between two vices - one an excess and one a deficiency. 
Politics 
Main article: Politics (Aristotle) 
In addition to his works on ethics, which address the individual, Aristotle addressed the city in 
his work titled Politics. Aristotle's conception of the city is organic, and he is considered one of 
the first to conceive of the city in this manner.[37] Aristotle considered the city to be a natural 
community. Moreover, he considered the city to be prior to the family which in turn is prior to 
the individual, i.e., last in the order of becoming, but first in the order of being . He is also 
famous for his statement that "man is by nature a political animal." Aristotle conceived of 
politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine, and as a collection of parts none of 
which can exist without the others. 
It should be noted that the modern understanding of a political community is that of the state. 
However, the state was foreign to Aristotle. He referred to political communities as cities. 
Aristotle understood a city as a political "partnership" and not one of a social contract (or 
compact) or a political community as understood by Niccolò Machiavelli. Subsequently, a city is 
created not to avoid injustice or for economic stability , but rather to live a good life: "The 
political partnership must be regarded, therefore, as being for the sake of noble actions, not for 
the sake of living together" . This can be distinguished from the social contract theory which 
individuals leave the state of nature because of "fear of violent death" or its "inconveniences."[38]
Rhetoric and poetics 
Main articles: Rhetoric (Aristotle) and Poetics (Aristotle) 
Aristotle considered epic poetry, tragedy, comedy, dithyrambic poetry and music to be imitative, 
each varying in imitation by media, object, and manner.[39] For example, music imitates with the 
media of rhythm and harmony, whereas dance imitates with rhythm alone, and poetry with 
language. The forms also differ in their object of imitation. Comedy, for instance, is a dramatic 
imitation of men worse than average; whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average. 
Lastly, the forms differ in their manner of imitation - through narrative or character, through 
change or no change, and through drama or no drama.[40] Aristotle believed that imitation is 
natural to mankind and constitutes one of mankind's advantages over animals.[41] 
While it is believed that Aristotle's Poetics comprised two books - one on comedy and one on 
tragedy - only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived. Aristotle taught that tragedy is 
composed of six elements: plot-structure, character, style, spectacle, and lyric poetry.[42] The 
characters in a tragedy are merely a means of driving the story; and the plot, not the characters, is 
the chief focus of tragedy. Tragedy is the imitation of action arousing pity and fear, and is meant 
to effect the catharsis of those same emotions. Aristotle concludes Poetics with a discussion on 
which, if either, is superior: epic or tragic mimesis. He suggests that because tragedy possesses 
all the attributes of an epic, possibly possesses additional attributes such as spectacle and music, 
is more unified, and achieves the aim of its mimesis in shorter scope, it can be considered 
superior to epic.[43] 
Aristotle was a keen systematic collector of riddles, folklore, and proverbs; he and his school had 
a special interest in the riddles of the Delphic Oracle and studied the fables of Aesop.[44] 
The loss of his works 
According to a distinction that originates with Aristotle himself, his writings are divisible into 
two groups: the "exoteric" and the "esoteric".[45] Most scholars have understood this as a 
distinction between works Aristotle intended for the public (exoteric), and the more technical 
works (esoteric) intended for the narrower audience of Aristotle's students and other 
philosophers who were familiar with the jargon and issues typical of the Platonic and 
Aristotelian schools. Another common assumption is that none of the exoteric works is extant - 
that all of Aristotle's extant writings are of the esoteric kind. Current knowledge of what exactly 
the exoteric writings were like is scant and dubious, though many of them may have been in 
dialogue form. (Fragments of some of Aristotle's dialogues have survived.) Perhaps it is to these 
that Cicero refers when he characterized Aristotle's writing style as "a river of gold";[46] it is hard 
for many modern readers to accept that one could seriously so admire the style of those works 
currently available to us.[47] However, some modern scholars have warned that we cannot know 
for certain that Cicero's praise was reserved specifically for the exoteric works; a few modern 
scholars have actually admired the concise writing style found in Aristotle's extant works.[48] 
One major question in the history of Aristotle's works, then, is how were the exoteric writings all 
lost, and how did the ones we now possess come to us?[49] The story of the original manuscripts
of the esoteric treatises is described by Strabo in his Geography and Plutarch in his Parallel 
Lives.[50] The manuscripts were left from Aristotle to his successor Theophrastus, who in turn 
willed them to Neleus of Scepsis. Neleus supposedly took the writings from Athens to Scepsis, 
where his heirs let them languish in a cellar until the first century BC, when Apellicon of Teos 
discovered and purchased the manuscripts, bringing them back to Athens. According to the story, 
Apellicon tried to repair some of the damage that was done during the manuscripts' stay in the 
basement, introducing a number of errors into the text. When Lucius Cornelius Sulla occupied 
Athens in 86 BC, he carried off the library of Apellicon to Rome, where they were first 
published in 60 BC by the grammarian Tyrannion of Amisus and then by philosopher 
Andronicus of Rhodes. 
Carnes Lord attributes the popular belief in this story to the fact that it provides "the most 
plausible explanation for the rapid eclipse of the Peripatetic school after the middle of the third 
century, and for the absence of widespread knowledge of the specialized treatises of Aristotle 
throughout the Hellenistic period, as well as for the sudden reappearance of a flourishing 
Aristotelianism during the first century B.C."[51] Lord voices a number of reservations concerning 
this story, however. First, the condition of the texts is far too good for them to have suffered 
considerable damage followed by Apellicon's inexpert attempt at repair. Second, there is 
"incontrovertible evidence," Lord says, that the treatises were in circulation during the time in 
which Strabo and Plutarch suggest they were confined within the cellar in Scepsis. Third, the 
definitive edition of Aristotle's texts seems to have been made in Athens some fifty years before 
Andronicus supposedly compiled his. And fourth, ancient library catalogues predating 
Andronicus' intervention list an Aristotelean corpus quite similar to the one we currently possess. 
Lord sees a number of post-Aristotelean interpolations in the Politics, for example, but is 
generally confident that the work has come down to us relatively intact. 
As the influence of the falsafa grew in the West, in part due to Gerard of Cremona's translations 
and the spread of Averroism, the demand for Aristotle's works grew. William of Moerbeke 
translated a number of them into Latin. When Thomas Aquinas wrote his theology, working 
from Moerbeke's translations, the demand for Aristotle's writings grew and the Greek 
manuscripts returned to the West, stimulating a revival of Aristotelianism in Europe, and 
ultimately revitalizing European thought through Muslim influence in Spain to fan the embers of 
the Renaissance. 
Legacy
Early Islamic portrayal of Aristotle 
Aristotle portrayed in the 1493 Nuremberg Chronicle as a 15th-century-A.D. scholar. 
Twenty-three hundred years after his death, Aristotle remains one of the most influential people 
who ever lived. He was the founder of formal logic, pioneered the study of zoology, and left 
every future scientist and philosopher in his debt through his contributions to the scientific 
method.[52][53] Despite these accolades, many of Aristotle's errors held back science considerably. 
Bertrand Russell notes that "almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an 
attack on some Aristotelian doctrine". Russell also refers to Aristotle's ethics as "repulsive", and 
calls his logic "as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy". Russell notes that these errors 
make it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle, until one remembers how large of an 
advance he made upon all of his predecessors.[54] 
The immediate influence of Aristotle's work was felt as the Lyceum grew into the Peripatetic 
school. Aristotle's notable students included Aristoxenus, Dicaearchus, Demetrius of Phalerum, 
Eudemos of Rhodes, Harpalus, Hephaestion, Meno, Mnason of Phocis, Nicomachus, and 
Theophrastus. Aristotle's influence over Alexander the Great is seen in the latter's bringing with 
him on his expedition a host of zoologists, botanists, and researchers. He had also learned a great 
deal about Persian customs and traditions from his teacher. Although his respect for Aristotle 
was diminished as his travels made it clear that much of Aristotle's geography was clearly 
wrong, when the old philosopher released his works to the public, Alexander complained "Thou 
hast not done well to publish thy acroamatic doctrines; for in what shall I surpass other men if 
those doctrines wherein I have been trained are to be all men's common property?"[55]
Aristotle is referred to as "The Philosopher" by Scholastic thinkers such as Thomas Aquinas. See 
Summa Theologica, Part I, Question 3, etc. These thinkers blended Aristotelian philosophy with 
Christianity, bringing the thought of Ancient Greece into the Middle Ages. It required a 
repudiation of some Aristotelian principles for the sciences and the arts to free themselves for the 
discovery of modern scientific laws and empirical methods. The medieval English poet Chaucer 
describes his student as being happy by having 
At his bedded hed 
Twenty books clothed in blake or red 
Of Aristotle and his philosophie 
The Italian poet Dante says of Aristotle in the first circles of hell, 
I saw the Master there of those who know, 
Amid the philosophic family, 
By all admired, and by all reverenced; 
There Plato too I saw, and Socrates, 
Who stood beside him closer than the rest. 
The German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche has been said to have taken nearly all of his 
political philosophy from Aristotle.[56] However implausible this is, it is certainly the case that 
Aristotle's rigid separation of action from production, and his justification of the subservience of 
slaves and others to the virtue - or arete - of a few justified the ideal of aristocracy. It is Martin 
Heidegger, not Nietzsche, who elaborated a new interpretation of Aristotle, intended to warrant 
his deconstruction of scholastic and philosophical tradition. More recently, Alasdair MacIntyre 
has attempted to reform what he calls the Aristotelian tradition in a way that is anti-elitist and 
capable of disputing the claims of both liberals and Nietzscheans.[57] 
List of Aristotle's works 
Main article: Corpus Aristotelicum 
Notes and References 
1. ^ Jonathan Barnes, "Life and Work" in The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle (1995), p. 
9. 
2. ^ McLeish, Kenneth (1999). Aristotle: The Great Philosophers. Routledge. p. 5. ISBN 0- 
415-92392-1. 
3. ^ Bertrand Russell, "A History of Western Philosophy", Simon & Schuster, 1972 
4. ^ Peter Green, Alexander of Macedon, 1991 University of California Press, Ltd. Oxford, 
England. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data, p.58-59 
5. ^ Peter Green, Alexander of Macedon, 1991 University of California Press, Ltd. Oxford, 
England. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data, p.379,459 
6. ^ William George Smith,Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology, vol. 
3, p. 88
7. ^ Bertrand Russell, "A History of Western Philosophy", Simon & Schuster, 1972 
8. ^ Neill, Alex; Aaron Ridley (1995). The Philosophy of Art: Readings Ancient and 
Modern. McGraw Hill. p. 488. http://www.amazon.com/dp/0070461929/. 
9. ^ Jones, W.T. (1980). The Classical Mind: A History of Western Philosophy. Harcourt 
Brace Jovanovich. p. 216. http://www.amazon.com/dp/0155383124/., cf. Vita Marciana 
41. 
10. ^ Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt by Hildegard Temporini, Wolfgang 
HaaseAristotle's Will 
11. ^ Bocheński, I. M. (1951). Ancient Formal Logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing 
Company. 
12. ^ a b Bocheński, 1951. 
13. ^ Rose, Lynn E. (1968). Aristotle's Syllogistic. Springfield: Charles C Thomas Publisher. 
14. ^ Jori, Alberto (2003). Aristotele. Milano: Bruno Mondadori Editore. 
15. ^ Aristotle, History of Animals, 2.3. 
16. ^ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 
17. ^ Aristotle, Meteorology 1.8, trans. E.W. Webster, rev. J. Barnes. 
18. ^ Burent, John. 1928. Platonism, Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 61, 103- 
104. 
19. ^ Aristotle, Physics 2.6 
20. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics VIII 1043a 10-30 
21. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics IX 1050a 5-10 
22. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics VIII 1045a-b 
23. ^ a b Singer, Charles. A short history of biology. Oxford 1931. 
24. ^ Emily Kearns, "Animals, knowledge about," in Oxford Classical Dictionary, 3rd ed., 
1996, p. 92. 
25. ^ Aristotle, of course, is not responsible for the later use made of this idea by clerics. 
26. ^ Mason, A History of the Sciences pp 43-44 
27. ^ Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought, pp 201-202; see also: Lovejoy, The Great 
Chain of Being 
28. ^ Aristotle, De Anima II 3 
29. ^ Mason, A History of the Sciences pp 45 
30. ^ Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy Vol. 1 pp. 348 
31. ^ Harding, Sandra; Merrill B. Hintikka (31 December 1999). Discovering Reality,: 
Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of 
Science. Springer. p. 372. http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/9027714967/. 
32. ^ Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought, pp 90-91; Mason, A History of the Sciences, 
p 46 
33. ^ Annas, Classical Greek Philosophy pp 252 
34. ^ Mason, A History of the Sciences pp 56 
35. ^ Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought, pp 90-94; quotation from p 91 
36. ^ Annas, Classical Greek Philosophy, p 252 
37. ^ Ebenstein, Alan; William Ebenstein (2002). Introduction to Political Thinkers. 
Wadsworth Group. p. 59. 
38. ^ For a different reading of social and economic processes in the Nicomacean Ethics and 
Politics see Polanyi, K. (1957) "Aristotle Discovers the Economy" in Primitive, Archaic 
and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi ed. G. Dalton, Boston 1971, 78-115
39. ^ Aristotle, Poetics I 1447a 
40. ^ Aristotle, Poetics III 
41. ^ Aristotle, Poetics IV 
42. ^ Aristotle, Poetics VI 
43. ^ Aristotle, Poetics XXVI 
44. ^ Temple, Olivia, and Temple, Robert (translators), The Complete Fables By Aesop 
Penguin Classics, 1998. ISBN 0140446494 Cf. Introduction, pp. xi-xii. 
45. ^ Jonathan Barnes, "Life and Work" in The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle (1995), p. 
12; Aristotle himself: Nichomachean Ethics 1102a26-27. Aristotle himself never uses the 
term "esoteric" or "acroamatic". For other passages where Aristotle speaks of exōterikoi 
logoi, see W. D. Ross, Aristotle's Metaphysics (1953), vol. 2, pp. 408-410. Ross defends 
an interpretation according to which the phrase, at least in Aristotle's own works, usually 
refers generally to "discussions not peculiar to the Peripatetic school", rather than to 
specific works of Aristotle's own. 
46. ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius (106BC-43BC). ""flumen orationis aureum fundens 
Aristoteles"". Academica. http://www2.cddc.vt.edu/gutenberg/1/4/9/7/14970/14970- 
h/14970-h.htm#BkII_119. Retrieved on 25 January 2007. 
47. ^ Barnes, "Life and Work", p. 12. 
48. ^ Barnes, "Roman Aristotle", in Gregory Nagy, Greek Literature, Routledge 2001, vol. 8, 
p. 174 n. 240. 
49. ^ The definitive, English study of these questions is Barnes, "Roman Aristotle". 
50. ^ "Sulla." 
51. ^ Lord, Carnes (1984). Introduction to the Politics, by Aristotle. Chicago: Chicago 
University Press. p. 11. 
52. ^ http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/34560/Aristotle 
53. ^ Durant, Will (1926 (2006)). The Story of Philosophy. United States: Simon & Schuster, 
Inc.. p. 92. ISBN 9780671739164. 
54. ^ Bertrand Russell, "A History of Western Philosophy", Simon & Schuster, 1972 
55. ^ Plutarch, Life of Alexander 
56. ^ Durant, p. 86 
57. ^ Kelvin Knight, Aristotelian Philosophy, Polity Press, 2007, passim. 
Further reading 
The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. The following references are only a small selection. 
· Ackrill J. L . 2001. Essays on Plato and Aristotle, Oxford University Press, USA 
· Adler, Mortimer J . (1978). Aristotle for Everybody. New York: Macmillan. A popular 
exposition for the general reader. 
· Bakalis Nikolaos. 2005. Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics 
Analysis and Fragments, Trafford Publishing ISBN 1-4120-4843-5 
· Barnes J. 1995. The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, Cambridge University Press 
· Bocheński, I. M . (1951). Ancient Formal Logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing 
Company.
· Bolotin, David (1998). An Approach to Aristotle's Physics: With Particular Attention to 
the Role of His Manner of Writing. Albany: SUNY Press. A contribution to our 
understanding of how to read Aristotle's scientific works. 
· Burnyeat, M. F . et al. 1979. Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics. Oxford: Sub-faculty 
of Philosophy 
· Chappell, V. 1973. Aristotle's Conception of Matter, Journal of Philosophy 70: 679-696 
· Code, Alan. 1995. Potentiality in Aristotle's Science and Metaphysics, Pacific 
Philosophical Quarterly 76 
· Frede, Michael. 1987. Essays in Ancient Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of 
Minnesota Press 
· Gill, Mary Louise. 1989. Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity. Princeton: 
Princeton University Press 
· Guthrie, W. K. C. (1981). A History of Greek Philosophy, Vol. 6. Cambridge University 
Press. 
· Halper, Edward C. (2007) One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 1: Books 
Alpha — Delta, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-21-6 
· Halper, Edward C. (2005) One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 2: The 
Central Books, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-05-6 
· Irwin, T. H. 1988. Aristotle's First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press 
· Jori, Alberto . 2003. Aristotele, Milano: Bruno Mondadori Editore (Prize 2003 of the 
"International Academy of the History of Science") ISBN 88-424-9737-1 
· Knight, Kelvin. 2007. Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to 
MacIntyre, Polity Press. 
· Lewis, Frank A. 1991. Substance and Predication in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge 
University Press. 
· Lloyd, G. E. R . 1968. Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of his Thought. Cambridge: 
Cambridge Univ. Pr., ISBN 0-521-09456-9. 
· Lord, Carnes. 1984. Introduction to The Politics, by Aristotle. Chicago: Chicago 
University Press. 
· Loux, Michael J. 1991. Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle's Metaphysics Ζ and Η. 
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press 
· Owen, G. E. L. 1965c. The Platonism of Aristotle, Proceedings of the British Academy 
50 125-150. Reprinted in J. Barnes, M. Schofield, and R. R. K. Sorabji (eds.), Articles on 
Aristotle, Vol 1. Science. London: Duckworth (1975). 14-34 
· Pangle, Lorraine Smith (2003). Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship. Cambridge: 
Cambridge University Press. Aristotle's conception of the deepest human relationship 
viewed in the light of the history of philosophic thought on friendship. 
· Reeve, C. D. C. 2000. Substantial Knowledge: Aristotle's Metaphysics. Indianapolis: 
Hackett. 
· Rose, Lynn E . (1968). Aristotle's Syllogistic. Springfield: Charles C Thomas Publisher. 
· Ross, Sir David (1995). Aristotle (6th ed. ed.). London: Routledge. An classic overview 
by one of Aristotle's most prominent English translators, in print since 1923. 
· Scaltsas, T. 1994. Substances and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics. Ithaca: Cornell 
University Press. 
· Strauss, Leo. "On Aristotle's Politics" (1964), in The City and Man, Chicago; Rand 
McNally.
· Taylor, Henry Osborn (1922). "Chapter 3: Aristotle's Biology". Greek Biology and 
Medicine. 
http://web.archive.org/web/20060327222953/http://www.ancientlibrary.com/medicine/00 
51.html. 
· Veatch, Henry B . (1974). Aristotle: A Contemporary Appreciation. Bloomington: Indiana 
U. Press. For the general reader. 
· Woods, M. J. 1991b. "Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle's Metaphysics." 
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy supplement. 41-56 
Terjemah 
Aristotle (Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης Aristotélēs) (384 SM - 322 SM) adalah seorang filsuf Yunani, 
seorang pelajar dari Plato dan guru dari Alexander the Great. He wrote on many subjects, 
including physics, metaphysics , poetry , theater, music, logic, rhetoric, politics, government, 
ethics, biology and zoology. Dia menulis di banyak mata pelajaran, termasuk fisika, metafisika, 
puisi, teater, musik, logika, retorika, politik, pemerintahan, etika, biologi dan zoology. 
Together with Plato and Socrates (Plato's teacher), Aristotle is one of the most important 
founding figures in Western philosophy . Bersama dengan Plato dan Socrates (guru Plato), 
Aristotle adalah salah satu yang paling penting dalam mendirikan tokoh filsafat Barat. He was 
the first to create a comprehensive system of Western philosophy, encompassing morality and 
aesthetics, logic and science, politics and metaphysics. Dia adalah yang pertama untuk membuat 
suatu sistem filsafat Barat, meliputi moralitas dan estetika, logika dan ilmu pengetahuan, politik 
dan metafisika. Aristotle's views on the physical sciences profoundly shaped medieval 
scholarship, and their influence extended well into the Renaissance , although they were 
ultimately replaced by modern physics . Aristotle's dilihat pada fisik ilmu profoundly abad 
berbentuk beasiswa, dan pengaruh mereka diperpanjang baik ke Renaisans, meskipun mereka 
akhirnya digantikan oleh fisika modern. In the biological sciences, some of his observations were 
only confirmed to be accurate in the nineteenth century. Dalam ilmu biologi, beberapa orang 
hanya pengamatan dikonfirmasi menjadi akurat dalam abad kesembilanbelas. His works contain 
the earliest known formal study of logic, which were incorporated in the late nineteenth century 
into modern formal logic . Karya-karyanya mengandung paling awal formal dikenal ilmu logika, 
yang tergabung pada akhir abad ke sembilan belas modern formal logika. In metaphysics, 
Aristotelianism had a profound influence on philosophical and theological thinking in the Islamic 
and Jewish traditions in the Middle Ages , and it continues to influence Christian theology , 
especially Eastern Orthodox theology , and the scholastic tradition of the Roman Catholic 
Church . Dalam metafisika, Aristotelianism memiliki pengaruh besar pada pemikiran filosofis 
dan teologi dalam tradisi Islam dan Yahudi di abad pertengahan, dan terus mempengaruhi teologi 
Kristen, khususnya teologi Ortodoks Timur, dan sekolah dari tradisi Gereja Katolik Roma. All 
aspects of Aristotle's philosophy continue to be the object of active academic study today. Semua 
aspek filosofi Aristotel terus menjadi objek studi akademis aktif hari ini.
Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues ( Cicero described his literary style 
as "a river of gold"), it is thought that the majority of his writings are now lost and only about 
one third of the original works have survived. [ 1 ] Walaupun Aristotle menulis banyak treatises 
elegan dan dialog (Cicero dijelaskan kepada sastra gaya sebagai "sungai emas"), ia berpikir 
bahwa sebagian besar tulisannya telah hilang dan hanya sekitar sepertiga dari karya asli yang 
bertahan hidup. [1] 
Contents Isi 
[hide] 
· 1 Life 1 Hidup 
· 2 Logic 2 Logic 
o 2.1 History Sejarah 2,1 
o 2.2 Analytics and the Organon 2,2 Analytics dan Organon 
· 3 Aristotle's scientific method 3 Aristotle's metode ilmiah 
· 4 Physics 4 Fisika 
o 4.1 The five elements 4.1 lima elemen 
o 4.2 Causality, The Four Causes 4,2 hubungan sebab dan akibat, Empat Penyebab 
o 4.3 Chance and spontaneity Kemungkinan 4,3 dan spontanitas 
· 5 Metaphysics 5 metafisika 
o 5.1 Substance, potentiality and actuality 5,1 Substansi, potensi dan actuality 
o 5.2 Universals and particulars 5,2 Universals dan fakta-fakta 
· 6 Biology and medicine 6 Biologi dan Obat 
o 6.1 Empirical research program 6,1 empiris program penelitian 
o 6.2 Classification of living things 6,2 Klasifikasi hidup hal 
o 6.3 Theory of biological forms and souls 6,3 Theory of biologi bentuk dan jiwa 
o 6.4 Aristotle's successor: Theophrastus 6,4 Aristotle's penerus: Theophrastus 
o 6.5 Influence on Hellenistic medicine Pengaruh 6,5 pada Helenistik obat 
· 7 Practical Philosophy 7 Praktis Filosofi 
o 7.1 Ethics 7,1 Kode Etik 
o 7.2 Politics 7,2 Politik 
o 7.3 Rhetoric and poetics 7,3 retorika dan poetics 
· 8 The loss of his works 8 Hilangnya karya-karyanya 
· 9 Legacy 9 Legacy 
· 10 List of Aristotle's works 10 Daftar Aristotle's works 
· 11 Notes and References 11 Catatan dan Referensi 
· 12 Further reading 12 Lebih lanjut membaca 
· 13 See also 13 Lihat juga 
· 14 External links 14 Pranala luar 
o 14.1 Collections of Aristotle's works Koleksi dari 14,1 Aristotle's works 
o 14.2 Articles on Aristotle Artikel pada 14,2 Aristotel 
Life Kehidupan
Aristotle was born in Stageira , Chalcidice , in 384 BC, about 55 km east of modern-day 
Thessaloniki . [ 2 ] His father, Nicomachus was the personal physician to King Amyntas of 
Macedon . Aristotle lahir di Stageira, Chalcidice, pada 384 SM, sekitar 55 kilometer sebelah 
timur modern hari Thessaloniki. [2] Ayahnya, Nicomachus adalah dokter pribadi ke Raja 
Amyntas dari Macedon. Aristotle was trained and educated as a member of the aristocracy . 
Aristotel telah dididik dan dilatih sebagai anggota dari aristokrasi. At about the age of eighteen, 
he went to Athens to continue his education at Plato's Academy . Pada usia sekitar delapan belas, 
dia pergi ke Jakarta untuk melanjutkan pendidikan di Akademi Plato's. Aristotle remained at the 
academy for nearly twenty years, not leaving until after Plato's death in 347 BC. Aristotel tetap 
di akademi selama hampir dua puluh tahun, tidak meninggalkan Plato sampai setelah kematian di 
347 SM. He then traveled with Xenocrates to the court of his friend Hermias of Atarneus in Asia 
Minor. Kemudian dia bepergian dengan Xenocrates ke pengadilan kepada teman Hermias dari 
Atarneus di Asia Minor. While in Asia, Aristotle traveled with Theophrastus to the island of 
Lesbos , where together they researched the botany and zoology of the island. Sementara di Asia, 
Aristotle bepergian dengan Theophrastus ke pulau Lesbos, di mana mereka bersama-sama 
dengan penelitian botani dan zoology dari pulau itu. Aristotle married Hermias's adoptive 
daughter (or niece) Pythias . Aristotel menikah Hermias's adoptive putri (atau keponakan) 
Pythias. She bore him a daughter, whom they named Pythias. Dia membosankan seorang anak 
perempuan, yang bernama Pythias mereka. Soon after Hermias' death, Aristotle was invited by 
Philip of Macedon to become tutor to Alexander the Great in 343 BC [ 3 ] Segera setelah Hermias' 
kematian, Aristotle diundang oleh Philip dari Macedon menjadi tutor untuk Alexander the Great 
pada 343 SM [3] 
During his time as the head of Macedon's royal academy, Aristotle gave lessons not only to 
Alexander, but also to two other future kings: Ptolemy and Cassander . Selama waktu sebagai 
kepala Macedon dari akademi kerajaan, Aristotle memberi pelajaran tidak hanya untuk 
Alexander, tetapi juga untuk masa depan dua raja: Ptolemy dan Cassander. In his Politics , 
Aristotle states that only one thing could justify monarchy, and that was if the virtue of the king 
and his family were greater than the virtue of the rest of the citizens put together. Dalam Politik, 
Aristotle menyatakan bahwa hanya satu hal yang dapat membenarkan monarki, dan yang jika 
kebaikan raja dan keluarganya yang lebih besar daripada kebaikan sisanya warga kota 
mengumpulkan. Tactfully, he included the young prince and his father in that category. Dgn 
bijaksana, dia termasuk anak raja dan ayahnya dalam kategori tersebut. Aristotle encouraged 
Alexander toward eastern conquest, and his attitude towards Persia was unabashedly 
ethnocentric. Aristotel didorong ke arah timur penaklukan Alexander, dan sikap terhadap Persia 
telah unabashedly ethnocentric. In one famous example, he counsels Alexander to be 'a leader to 
the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians, to look after the former as after friends and relatives, 
and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants'. [ 4 ] Near the end of Alexander's life he began 
to suspect plots, and threatened Aristotle in letters. Dalam satu contoh terkenal, Alexander 
counsels ia akan menjadi 'pemimpin ke Yunani dan orang lalim kepada barbarians, untuk 
memelihara setelah mantan sebagai teman dan keluarga, dan untuk menangani dengan kedua 
sebagai dengan binatang atau tanaman. [4] dekat akhir Alexander kehidupan dia mulai mencurigai 
plots, dan terancam di Aristotel huruf. Aristotle had made no secret of his contempt for 
Alexander's pretense of divinity, and the king had executed Aristotle's grand-nephew 
Callisthenes as a traitor. Aristotel telah dibuat tidak rahasia orang hina untuk Alexander dari 
tuntutan dari keilahian, dan raja telah dijalankan Aristotle's grand-keponakan Callisthenes
sebagai pengkhianat. A widespread tradition in antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in 
Alexander's death, but there is little evidence for this. [ 5 ] J luas dalam tradisi jaman dahulu dari 
diputar Aristotel diduga berperan dalam Alexander kematian, tetapi ada sedikit bukti untuk ini. [5] 
By 335 BC he had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the Lyceum . 
335 SM oleh dia kembali ke Jakarta, mendirikan sekolah itu sendiri dikenal sebagai kamar 
bacaan. Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years. Aristotel kursus 
dilakukan di sekolah selama dua belas tahun. While in Athens, his wife Pythias died, and 
Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stageira , who bore him a son whom he named after 
his father, Nicomachus . Sedangkan di Jakarta, istrinya Pythias meninggal, Aristotle dan menjadi 
terlibat dengan Herpyllis dari Stageira, yang membosankan dia seorang anak laki-laki yang 
dinamakannya setelah ayahnya, Nicomachus. According to the Suda , he also had an eromenos , 
Palaephatus of Abydus . [ 6 ] Menurut Suda, dia juga memiliki eromenos, Palaephatus dari 
Abydus. [6] 
It is during this period in Athens from 335 BC to 323 BC when Aristotle is believed to have 
composed many of his works. [ 7 ] Aristotle wrote many dialogues, only fragments of which 
survived. Adalah selama periode ini di Athena dari 335 SM ke 323 SM ketika Aristotel diyakini 
memiliki banyak terdiri dari karya-karyanya. [7] Aristotle menulis banyak dialog, hanya fragmen 
yang selamat. The works that have survived are in treatise form and were not, for the most part, 
intended for widespread publication, as they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his 
students. Pekerjaan yang telah bertahan dalam risalah formulir dan tidak, sebagian besar, yang 
dimaksudkan untuk publikasi luas, karena biasanya pemikiran untuk kuliah bantu untuk siswa. 
His most important treatises include Physics , Metaphysics , Nicomachean Ethics , Politics , De 
Anima (On the Soul) and Poetics . His paling penting termasuk treatises Fisika, metaphysics, 
Nicomachean Etika, Politik, De anima (On the Soul) dan Poetics. 
Aristotle not only studied almost every subject possible at the time, but made significant 
contributions to most of them. Aristotle tidak hanya belajar mata pelajaran yang mungkin hampir 
setiap saat, tetapi kontribusi yang signifikan kebanyakan mereka. In physical science, Aristotle 
studied anatomy, astronomy, economics, embryology , geography, geology, meteorology, 
physics and zoology. Dalam ilmu fisik, Aristotle mempelajari anatomi, astronomi, ekonomi, 
embriologi, geografi, geologi, meteorologi, fisika dan zoology. In philosophy, he wrote on 
aesthetics, ethics, government, metaphysics, politics, psychology, rhetoric and theology. Dalam 
filsafat, dia wrote estetika, etika, pemerintah, metafisika, politik, psikologi, retorika dan teologi. 
He also studied education, foreign customs, literature and poetry. Dia juga belajar pendidikan, 
adat asing, sastra dan puisi. His combined works constitute a virtual encyclopedia of Greek 
knowledge. Ia bekerja merupakan gabungan virtual ensiklopedia pengetahuan dari Yunani. It has 
been suggested that Aristotle was probably the last person to know everything there was to be 
known in his own time. [ 8 ] Telah menyarankan bahwa Aristotle mungkin terakhir orang 
mengetahui segala sesuatu ada dikenal dalam waktu sendiri. [8] 
Upon Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens once again flared. Eurymedon the 
hierophant denounced Aristotle for not holding the gods in honor. Setelah kematian Alexander, 
sentimen anti-Macedonia di Jakarta sekali lagi flared. Eurymedon yang hierophant denounced 
Aristotle untuk tidak memegang allah dalam kehormatan. Aristotle fled the city to his mother's
family estate in Chalcis , explaining, "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against 
philosophy ," [ 9 ] a reference to Athens's prior trial and execution of Socrates. Aristotel melarikan 
diri ke kota ibunya keluarga estate di Chalcis, menjelaskan, "Saya tidak akan mengizinkan 
Athenians berdosa dua kali terhadap filsafat," [9] referensi sebelumnya dari Jakarta ke pengadilan 
dan pelaksanaan Socrates. However, he died in Euboea of natural causes within the year (in 322 
BC). Namun, ia meninggal di Euboea penyebab dari alam dalam tahun (pada 322 sebelum 
masehi). Aristotle named chief executor his student Antipater and left a will in which he asked to 
be buried next to his wife. [ 10 ] Aristotel bernama ketua pelaksana his siswa Antipater dan kiri 
yang akan di mana ia harus dikubur di samping istrinya. [10] 
Logic Logika 
Main article: Term logic Artikel utama: Istilah logika 
For more details on this topic, see Non-Aristotelian logic . Untuk informasi lebih rinci 
tentang topik ini, lihat Non-Aristotel logika. 
Aristotle's conception of logic was the dominant form of logic until 19th century advances in 
mathematical logic . Kant stated in the Critique of Pure Reason that Aristotle's theory of logic 
completely accounted for the core of deductive inference. Aristotle's konsep dari logika dominan 
adalah bentuk logika sampai abad ke-19 kemajuan dalam logika matematika. Kant dalam 
Critique of Pure Reason yang Aristotle's teori logika sepenuhnya merupakan inti dari 
kesimpulan deduktif. 
History Sejarah 
Aristotle "says that 'on the subject of reasoning' he 'had nothing else on an earlier date to speak 
of'". [ 11 ] However, Plato reports that syntax was devised before him, by Prodicus of Ceos , who 
was concerned by the correct use of words. Aristotle "mengatakan bahwa 'pada subyek 
reasoning' dia 'sudah tidak ada lagi pada tanggal yang lebih awal untuk berbicara tentang'". [11] 
Namun, Plato laporan bahwa sintaks telah dibuat sebelum dia, oleh Prodicus dari Ceos, yang 
bersangkutan dengan benar menggunakan kata-kata. Logic seems to have emerged from 
dialectics ; the earlier philosophers made frequent use of concepts like reductio ad absurdum in 
their discussions, but never truly understood the logical implications. Logika tampaknya telah 
muncul dari dialektika, yang sebelumnya dilakukan filosof sering menggunakan konsep seperti 
reductio iklan absurdum dalam diskusi mereka, tetapi tidak pernah benar-benar memahami 
implikasi logis. Even Plato had difficulties with logic; although he had a reasonable conception 
of a deduction system, he could never actually construct one and relied instead on his dialectic . 
[ 12 ] Plato believed that deduction would simply follow from premises , hence he focused on 
maintaining solid premises so that the conclusion would logically follow. Plato bahkan pernah 
kesulitan dengan logika, walaupun ia memiliki konsep yang wajar deduction sistem, ia tidak 
pernah benar-benar dapat membangun dan diandalkan, bukan pada dialectic. [12] Plato percaya 
bahwa deduction akan cukup ikuti dari lokasi, maka ia fokus pada pemeliharaan solid lokasi 
sehingga kesimpulan logis akan mengikuti. Consequently, Plato realized that a method for 
obtaining conclusions would be most beneficial. Akibatnya, Plato menyadari bahwa metode 
untuk memperoleh kesimpulan akan paling bermanfaat. He never succeeded in devising such a 
method, but his best attempt was published in his book Sophist , where he introduced his division
method. [ 13 ] Ia tidak pernah berhasil dalam suatu metode devising, tapi ia mencoba terbaik 
dimuat dalam bukunya pandangannya, di mana dia diperkenalkan kepada divisi metode. [13] 
Analytics and the Organon Analisis dan Organon 
Main article: Organon Artikel utama: Organon 
What we today call Aristotelian logic , Aristotle himself would have labeled "analytics". Apa 
yang kita panggil hari ini Aristotel logika, Aristotle dirinya akan berlabel "analisis". The term 
"logic" he reserved to mean dialectics . Istilah "logika" berarti ia reserved dialektika. Most of 
Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, since it was most likely edited by students 
and later lecturers. Sebagian besar dari pekerjaan Aristotle mungkin tidak dalam bentuk aslinya, 
karena kemungkinan besar diedit oleh mahasiswa dan dosen nantinya. The logical works of 
Aristotle were compiled into six books in about the early 1st century AD: Yang logis dari 
Aristotle telah dikompilasi ke dalam enam buku sekitar awal abad 1. AD: 
1. Categories Kategori 
2. On Interpretation Pada Interpretation 
3. Prior Analytics Sebelum Analytics 
4. Posterior Analytics Posterior Analytics 
5. Topics Topik 
6. On Sophistical Refutations Pada Sophistical Refutations 
The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this 
list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. Pesanan buku-buku (atau ajaran dari 
mereka yang terdiri) tidak pasti, namun daftar ini adalah berasal dari analisis dari tulisan-tulisan 
Aristotle. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the Categories, to the study of 
more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the Analytics) and dialectics (in the Topics and 
Sophistical Refutations). It goes dari dasar, analisis sederhana istilah dalam Kategori, untuk studi 
yang lebih kompleks bentuk, yaitu, syllogisms (dalam Analytics) dan dialektika (dalam Topik 
dan Sophistical Refutations). There is one volume of Aristotle's concerning logic not found in the 
Organon , namely the fourth book of Metaphysics. . [ 12 ] Ada satu volume Aristotle's tentang 
logika tidak ditemukan di Organon, yaitu empat buku metafisika.. [12] 
Aristotle's scientific method Aristotle's metode ilmiah
Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of The School of Athens , a fresco by Raphael . Plato 
(kiri) dan Aristotle (kanan), sebuah detail di School of Athens, sebuah lukisan dinding oleh 
Raphael. Aristotle gestures to the earth, representing his belief in knowledge through empirical 
observation and experience, while holding a copy of his Nicomachean Ethics in his hand, whilst 
Plato gestures to the heavens, representing his belief in The Forms . Aristotel gerak-gerik ke 
bumi, yang merupakan kepercayaan kepada pengetahuan melalui pengamatan dan pengalaman 
empiris, sementara memegang salinan nya Nicomachean Etika di tangannya, sementara gerak-gerik 
Plato ke langit, ia mewakili kepercayaan di Formulir. 
For more details on this topic, see Aristotle's theory of universals . Untuk informasi lebih 
rinci tentang topik ini, lihat dari teori Aristotle universals. 
Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the universal . Seperti itu guru Plato, 
Aristotle filosofi bertujuan yang universal. Aristotle, however, found the universal in particular 
things, which he called the essence of things, while Plato finds that the universal exists apart 
from particular things, and is related to them as their prototype or exemplar . Aristotel Namun, 
menemukan universal khususnya hal-hal yang ia disebut inti dari sesuatu, sedangkan Plato 
menemukan bahwa ada yang universal selain dari hal-hal tertentu, dan berhubungan dengan 
mereka sebagai prototipe atau contoh. For Aristotle, therefore, philosophic method implies the 
ascent from the study of particular phenomena to the knowledge of essences, while for Plato 
philosophic method means the descent from a knowledge of universal Forms (or ideas) to a 
contemplation of particular imitations of these. Aristotel Untuk itu, metode filosofis yang 
menunjukkan kenaikan dari studi khusus untuk fenomena pengetahuan essences, sedangkan 
untuk metode filosofis Plato berarti keturunan dari pengetahuan tentang universal Formulir (atau 
gagasan) ke kontemplasi tertentu imitations ini. For Aristotle, "form" still refers to the 
unconditional basis of phenomena but is "instantiated" in a particular substance (see Universals 
and particulars , below). Untuk Aristotel, "bentuk" masih merujuk pada tak bersyarat dasar 
fenomena tetapi "instantiated" dalam substansi tertentu (lihat Universals dan fakta-fakta, di 
bawah). In a certain sense, Aristotle's method is both inductive and deductive , while Plato's is 
essentially deductive from a priori principles. [ 14 ] Dalam beberapa hal, Aristotle dari kedua 
metode induktif dan deduktif, sementara pada dasarnya adalah Plato's deduktif dari priori 
prinsip. [14] 
In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the 
phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, 
biology and other natural sciences. Dalam terminologi Aristotle's, "filosofi alam" adalah cabang 
filosofi yang meneliti fenomena alam di dunia, dan mencakup bidang yang akan hari ini 
dianggap sebagai fisika, biologi dan ilmu alam lainnya. In modern times, the scope of 
philosophy has become limited to more generic or abstract inquiries, such as ethics and 
metaphysics, in which logic plays a major role. Dalam modern, lingkup filsafat telah menjadi 
terbatas untuk lebih umum atau abstrak inquiries, seperti etika dan metafisika, dimana logika 
memainkan peran utama. Today's philosophy tends to exclude empirical study of the natural 
world by means of the scientific method . Today filosofi cenderung mengecualikan empiris ilmu 
alam dunia dengan cara yang metode ilmiah. In contrast, Aristotle's philosophical endeavors 
encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. Sebaliknya, Aristotle's filosofis berusaha 
mencakup hampir semua aspek dari penyelidikan intelektual.
In the larger sense of the word, Aristotle makes philosophy coextensive with reasoning, which he 
also would describe as "science". Lebih besar dalam arti kata, menjadikan filosofi Aristotel 
coextensive dengan alasan, dia juga yang akan menjelaskan sebagai "ilmu". Note, however, that 
his use of the term science carries a different meaning than that covered by the term " scientific 
method ". Namun, perlu diketahui bahwa penggunaan istilah ilmu membawa makna yang 
berbeda dari yang tercakup dalam istilah "metode ilmiah". For Aristotle, "all science ( dianoia ) 
is either practical, poetical or theoretical" ( Metaphysics 1025b25). Untuk Aristotel, "semua ilmu 
(dianoia) adalah salah satu praktis, puitis atau teoritis" (metaphysics 1025b25). By practical 
science, he means ethics and politics; by poetical science, he means the study of poetry and the 
other fine arts; by theoretical science, he means physics, mathematics and metaphysics. Praktis 
oleh ilmu pengetahuan, berarti ia etika dan politik; puitis oleh ilmu pengetahuan, berarti ia 
belajar puisi dan seni rupa yang lain; oleh teori ilmu pengetahuan, berarti ia fisika, matematika 
dan metafisika. 
If logic (or "analytics") is regarded as a study preliminary to philosophy, the divisions of 
Aristotelian philosophy would consist of: (1) Logic ; (2) Theoretical Philosophy, including 
Metaphysics, Physics, Mathematics, (3) Practical Philosophy and (4) Poetical Philosophy. Jika 
logika (atau "analisis") yang dianggap sebagai sebuah awal untuk belajar filsafat, maka divisi 
dari filosofi Aristotel akan terdiri dari: (1) Logika; (2) Theoretical Philosophy, termasuk 
metafisika, Fisika, Matematika, (3) praktis dan Filosofi (4) Filosofi puitis. 
In the period between his two stays in Athens, between his times at the Academy and the 
Lyceum, Aristotle conducted most of the scientific thinking and research for which he is 
renowned today. Pada periode antara dua tetap di Jakarta, antara nya kali di Akademi dan kamar 
bacaan, Aristotle dilakukan sebagian besar berpikir dan penelitian ilmiah yang ia terkenal hari 
ini. In fact, most of Aristotle's life was devoted to the study of the objects of natural science. 
Bahkan, sebagian besar dari Aristotle Hidup dikhususkan untuk ilmu obyek dari ilmu alam. 
Aristotle's metaphysics contains observations on the nature of numbers but he made no original 
contributions to mathematics. Aristotle's metaphysics berisi observasi pada sifat nomor tetapi ia 
tidak asli kontribusi kepada matematika. He did, however, perform original research in the 
natural sciences, eg, botany, zoology, physics, astronomy, chemistry, meteorology, and several 
other sciences. Dia, bagaimanapun, melakukan penelitian asli dalam ilmu alam, misalnya, botani, 
zoology, fisika, astronomi, kimia, meteorologi, dan beberapa ilmu lainnya. 
Aristotle's writings on science are largely qualitative, as opposed to quantitative. Aristotel dari 
tulisan-tulisan tentang ilmu pengetahuan yang sangat kualitatif, karena bertentangan dengan 
kuantitatif. Beginning in the sixteenth century, scientists began applying mathematics to the 
physical sciences, and Aristotle's work in this area was deemed hopelessly inadequate. Pada awal 
abad keenambelas, ilmuwan matematika untuk mulai menerapkan ilmu yang fisik, dan Aristotle's 
bekerja di daerah ini hopelessly dianggap kurang memadai. His failings were largely due to the 
absence of concepts like mass, velocity, force and temperature. His failings yang sebagian besar 
disebabkan oleh tidak adanya konsep seperti massa, kecepatan, kekuatan dan suhu. He had a 
conception of speed and temperature, but no quantitative understanding of them, which was 
partly due to the absence of basic experimental devices, like clocks and thermometers. Dia 
memiliki konsep dari kecepatan dan suhu, tapi tidak ada kuantitatif pemahaman mereka, yang 
sebagian karena tidak adanya dasar eksperimental perangkat, seperti jam dan termometer.
A green and red Perseid meteor is striking the sky just below the Milky Way in August 2007. J 
hijau dan merah Perseid meteor mengesankan adalah tepat di bawah langit yang Bimasakti pada 
bulan Agustus 2007. 
His writings provide an account of many scientific observations, a mixture of precocious 
accuracy and curious errors. Tulisannya memberikan banyak rekening ilmiah observasi, 
campuran sebelum waktunya curious akurasi dan kesalahan. For example, in his History of 
Animals he claimed that human males have more teeth than females. [ 15 ] In a similar vein, John 
Philoponus , and later Galileo , showed by simple experiments that Aristotle's theory that a 
heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect. [ 16 ] On the other hand, Aristotle 
refuted Democritus 's claim that the Milky Way was made up of "those stars which are shaded by 
the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out (correctly, even if such reasoning was bound to be 
dismissed for a long time) that, given "current astronomical demonstrations" that "the size of the 
sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times 
greater than that of the sun, then...the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of 
them." [ 17 ] Misalnya, dalam Sejarah Binatang ia menyatakan bahwa manusia laki-laki memiliki 
lebih dari gigi perempuan. [15] Dalam nada yang sama, John Philoponus, dan kemudian Galileo, 
menunjukkan bahwa percobaan sederhana oleh Aristotle's teori bahwa benda berat jatuh lebih 
cepat dari yang ringan objek tidak benar. [16] Di sisi lain, Aristotle refuted Democritus' s klaim 
bahwa Bimasakti dibuat dari "orang-bintang yang berbayang dari oleh bumi dari sinar matahari," 
pointing out (dengan benar, bahkan jika reasoning telah terikat akan diberhentikan untuk waktu 
yang lama) itu, diberikan "sekarang astronomi demonstrasi" yang "ukuran matahari lebih besar 
daripada yang di bumi dan jarak dari bintang-bintang dari bumi berkali-kali lebih besar dari yang 
matahari, maka ... matahari bersinar di seluruh bumi dan bintang layar none of them. "[17] 
In places, Aristotle goes too far in deriving 'laws of the universe' from simple observation and 
over-stretched reason . Di tempat, Aristotle pergi terlalu jauh dalam deriving 'hukum alam 
semesta' dari pengamatan sederhana dan over-stretched alasan. Today's scientific method 
assumes that such thinking without sufficient facts is ineffective, and that discerning the validity 
of one's hypothesis requires far more rigorous experimentation than that which Aristotle used to 
support his laws. Hari metode ilmiah dengan menganggap bahwa tanpa memikirkan fakta-fakta 
yang cukup efektif, dan yang cerdas validitas satu dari hipotesa memerlukan eksperimentasi jauh 
lebih ketat daripada yang Aristotel digunakan untuk mendukung undang-undang. 
Aristotle also had some scientific blind spots. Aristotle juga mempunyai beberapa ilmiah buta 
tempat itu. He posited a geocentric cosmology that we may discern in selections of the 
Metaphysics , which was widely accepted up until the 1500s. Dia posited yang geocentric
kosmologi bahwa kami dapat memahami dalam pilihan dari metafisika, yang diterima secara luas 
sampai 1500s. From the 3rd century to the 1500s, the dominant view held that the Earth was the 
center of the universe ( geocentrism ). 3. Dari abad ke 1500s, yang dominan diselenggarakan 
melihat bahwa Bumi adalah pusat alam semesta (geocentrism). 
Since he was perhaps the philosopher most respected by European thinkers during and after the 
Renaissance, these thinkers often took Aristotle's erroneous positions as given, which held back 
science in this epoch. [ 18 ] However, Aristotle's scientific shortcomings should not mislead one 
into forgetting his great advances in the many scientific fields. Sejak dia mungkin filsuf yang 
paling dihormati oleh pemikir Eropa selama dan setelah Renaissance, pemikir ini sering 
mengambil Aristotle's salah posisi seperti yang diberikan, yang diselenggarakan kembali sains di 
masa ini. [18] Namun, Aristotle's ilmiah kekurangan seharusnya tidak menyesatkan satu menjadi 
melupakan dia kemajuan besar dalam berbagai bidang ilmu. For instance, he founded logic as a 
formal science and created foundations to biology that were not superseded for two millennia. 
Sebagai contoh, ia didirikan sebagai logika formal sains dan membuat yayasan untuk biologi 
yang tidak superseded selama dua ribuan tahun. Moreover, he introduced the fundamental notion 
that nature is composed of things that change and that studying such changes can provide useful 
knowledge of underlying constants. Selain itu, dia memperkenalkan mendasar bahwa alam 
terdiri dari hal-hal yang berubah dan perubahan yang belajar seperti itu dapat memberikan 
pengetahuan yang berguna konstan. 
Physics Fisika 
Main article: Physics (Aristotle) Artikel utama: Fisika (Aristotle) 
The five elements Lima elemen 
Main article: Classical element Artikel utama: Klasik elemen 
· Fire , which is hot and dry. Api, yang panas dan kering. 
· Earth , which is cold and dry. Bumi, yang dingin dan kering. 
· Air , which is hot and wet. Udara yang panas dan basah. 
· Water , which is cold and wet. Air yang dingin dan basah. 
· Aether , which is the divine substance that makes up the heavenly spheres and heavenly 
bodies (stars and planets). Aether, yang merupakan substansi ilahi yang membuat sampai 
di langit spheres dan badan-badan langit (bintang dan planets). 
Each of the four earthly elements has its natural place; the earth at the centre of the universe, 
then water, then air, then fire. Masing-masing dari empat elemen dunia memiliki tempat alam; 
bumi di pusat alam semesta, maka air, maka udara, maka api. When they are out of their natural 
place they have natural motion, requiring no external cause, which is towards that place; so 
bodies sink in water, air bubbles up, rain falls, flame rises in air. Apabila mereka dari tempat 
mereka alami alam gerakan mereka, tidak memerlukan penyebab eksternal, yang menuju tempat 
itu, maka tubuh masuk ke dalam air, sampai gelembung udara, hujan, api di udara meningkat. 
The heavenly element has perpetual circular motion. Di langit yang terus-elemen gerakan 
melingkar.
Causality, The Four Causes Hubungan sebab dan akibat, Empat Penyebab 
Main article: Four causes Artikel utama: Empat menyebabkan 
· The material cause is that from which a thing comes into existence as from its part, 
constituents, substratum or materials. Materi yang menyebabkan adalah sebuah hal yang 
datang ke dalam keberadaan sebagai bagian dari, konstituen, atau bahan-bahan dasar. 
This reduces the explanation of causes to the parts (factors, elements, constituents, 
ingredients) forming the whole (system, structure, compound, complex, composite, or 
combination), a relationship known as the part-whole causation. Ini akan mengurangi 
penjelasan tentang penyebab ke bagian (faktor, elemen, konstituen, bahan) membentuk 
keseluruhan (sistem, struktur, kompleks, rumit, komposit, atau kombinasi), sebuah 
hubungan yang dikenal sebagai bagian-hal menyebabkan seluruh. Simply put it is the 
influence of the material substances on the event. Simply put it is pengaruh materi bahan 
pada acara tersebut. So imagine two dominos, the first of which is lighter. Jadi bayangkan 
dua dominos, pertama yang lebih ringan. The first is knocked over into the second but 
does not have enough power to knock it over, this is Material cause. Yang pertama adalah 
knocked over menjadi yang kedua tetapi tidak memiliki cukup kuasa untuk merobohkan 
lebih dari itu, hal ini menyebabkan Bahan. 
· The formal cause tells us what a thing is, that any thing is determined by the definition, 
form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis or archetype. Formal menyebabkan memberitahu 
kami apa yang hal itu, bahwa hal itu ditentukan oleh definisi, bentuk, pola, inti, seluruh, 
sintesis atau pola dasar. It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental 
principles or general laws, as the whole (ie, macrostructure) is the cause of its parts, a 
relationship known as the whole-part causation. It meliputi rekening penyebab dari segi 
prinsip-prinsip umum atau undang-undang, sebagai keseluruhan (yakni, macrostructure) 
adalah penyebab komponen, yang dikenal sebagai hubungan seluruh bagian-hal 
menyebabkan. Plainly put it is the influence of the form (essence) of the things on the 
event. Terangnya menaruhnya adalah pengaruh dalam bentuk (inti) dari hal-hal di acara 
itu. So take the two dominos again except this time the second is shaped to prevent it 
from falling *eg. Jadi mengambil dua dominos lagi kecuali kali ini adalah yang kedua 
berbentuk untuk mencegah dari jatuh * misalnya. triangular.* this is formal cause. 
segitiga .* ini menyebabkan formal. 
· The efficient cause is that from which the change or the ending of the change first starts. 
Yang efisien adalah bahwa dari mana perubahan atau akhir dari perubahan pertama 
dimulai. It identifies 'what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is 
changed' and so suggests all sorts of agents, nonliving or living, acting as the sources of 
change or movement or rest. It mengenalpasti 'apa yang membuat apa yang dilakukan dan 
apa yang menyebabkan perubahan apa yang berubah' dan menyarankan agar semua jenis 
agen, yg tdk hidup atau hidup, yang bertindak sebagai sumber perubahan atau gerakan 
atau beristirahat. Representing the current understanding of causality as the relation of 
cause and effect, this covers the modern definitions of "cause" as either the agent or 
agency or particular events or states of affairs. Mewakili saat ini pemahaman tentang 
hubungan sebab dan akibat sebagai hubungan yang menyebabkan dan efek, yang modern 
ini mencakup definisi "menyebabkan" sebagai salah satu agen atau agen atau peristiwa 
tertentu atau urusan negara. More simply again that which immediately sets the thing in 
motion. Dengan kata lain lagi yang segera menentukan hal dalam gerakan. So take the
two dominos this time of equal weighting, the first is knocked over causing the second 
also to fall over. Jadi mengambil dua dominos ini waktu sama bobot, yang pertama 
adalah melalui knocked menyebabkan kedua juga jatuh. This is effectively efficient 
cause. Hal ini menyebabkan secara efektif efisien. 
· The final cause is that for the sake of which a thing exists or is done, including both 
purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. Akhir adalah bahwa untuk 
kepentingan apapun yang ada atau dilakukan, termasuk kedua sengaja dan tindakan 
instrumental dan kegiatan. The final cause or telos is the purpose or end that something is 
supposed to serve, or it is that from which and that to which the change is. Akhir 
menyebabkan atau telos adalah tujuan akhir atau sesuatu yang digunakan untuk melayani, 
atau adalah bahwa dari mana dan ke mana perubahan itu. This also covers modern ideas 
of mental causation involving such psychological causes as volition, need, motivation, or 
motives, rational, irrational, ethical, all that gives purpose to behavior. Ini juga mencakup 
ide-ide modern dari hal menyebabkan mental melibatkan sebagai penyebab psikologis 
seperti kemauan, kebutuhan, motivasi, atau motif, rasional, irasional, etika, yang 
tujuannya untuk memberikan perilaku. 
Additionally, things can be causes of one another, causing each other reciprocally, as hard work 
causes fitness and vice versa, although not in the same way or function, the one is as the 
beginning of change, the other as the goal. Selain itu, hal ini dapat menyebabkan dari satu sama 
lain, sehingga satu sama lain begitu, kerja keras sebagai penyebab kebugaran dan sebaliknya, 
walaupun tidak dengan cara yang sama atau fungsi, yang satu adalah sebagai awal dari 
perubahan, yang lain sebagai tujuan. (Thus Aristotle first suggested a reciprocal or circular 
causality as a relation of mutual dependence or influence of cause upon effect). (Oleh karena itu 
disarankan Aristotel pertama yang timbal atau surat edaran hubungan sebab dan akibat sebagai 
hubungan yang saling ketergantungan atau pengaruh atas menimbulkan efek). Moreover, 
Aristotle indicated that the same thing can be the cause of contrary effects; its presence and 
absence may result in different outcomes. Selain itu, Aristotle menunjukkan bahwa hal yang 
sama yang dapat menyebabkan efek yang berlawanan; kehadiran dan ketidakhadiran yang dapat 
menyebabkan hasil yang berbeda. Simply it is the goal or purpose that brings about an event (not 
necessarily a mental goal). Cukup adalah tujuan atau tujuan yang membawa tentang aktivitas 
(mental yang belum tentu tujuan). Taking our two dominos, it requires someone to intentionally 
knock the dominos over as they cannot fall themselves. Mengambil dua dominos, ia memerlukan 
seseorang untuk sengaja membuat dominos atas karena mereka tidak bisa jatuh sendiri. 
Aristotle marked two modes of causation: proper (prior) causation and accidental (chance) 
causation. Aristotel ditandai dari dua hal menyebabkan mode: tepat (sebelumnya) dan hal 
menyebabkan kebetulan (kemungkinan) hal menyebabkan. All causes, proper and incidental, can 
be spoken as potential or as actual, particular or generic. Semua penyebab, tepat dan insidentil, 
dapat digunakan sebagai potensi atau sebenarnya, khusus atau umum. The same language refers 
to the effects of causes, so that generic effects assigned to generic causes, particular effects to 
particular causes, operating causes to actual effects. Bahasa yang sama merujuk pada efek dari 
penyebab, sehingga efek yang ditugaskan untuk umum penyebab umum, khususnya 
menyebabkan efek tertentu, operasi untuk menyebabkan efek yang sebenarnya. Essentially, 
causality does not suggest a temporal relation between the cause and the effect. Pada dasarnya, 
hubungan sebab dan akibat tidak menyarankan sementara hubungan antara penyebab dan efek.
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles
Aristotles

Mais conteúdo relacionado

Mais procurados

Mais procurados (19)

Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
3 Aristotle's Biology
3 Aristotle's Biology3 Aristotle's Biology
3 Aristotle's Biology
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
Aristotle's Politics (Summary)
Aristotle's Politics (Summary)Aristotle's Politics (Summary)
Aristotle's Politics (Summary)
 
Aristotle categories biology
Aristotle categories biology Aristotle categories biology
Aristotle categories biology
 
Aristotle political philosophy - western political thought
Aristotle political philosophy - western political thoughtAristotle political philosophy - western political thought
Aristotle political philosophy - western political thought
 
Atif presentation aristotle
Atif presentation aristotleAtif presentation aristotle
Atif presentation aristotle
 
Reina aristotle
Reina aristotleReina aristotle
Reina aristotle
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
Aristotle and the Politics
Aristotle and the PoliticsAristotle and the Politics
Aristotle and the Politics
 
Aristotle (384-322 BCE)
Aristotle (384-322 BCE)Aristotle (384-322 BCE)
Aristotle (384-322 BCE)
 
Aristotle Reina 2011
Aristotle Reina 2011Aristotle Reina 2011
Aristotle Reina 2011
 
Greek mathematics
Greek mathematicsGreek mathematics
Greek mathematics
 
2 Aristotle Logic
2 Aristotle Logic2 Aristotle Logic
2 Aristotle Logic
 
Aristotle's life and major contributions
Aristotle's life and major contributions Aristotle's life and major contributions
Aristotle's life and major contributions
 
The greek philosophers - AN OVERVIEW
The greek philosophers - AN OVERVIEWThe greek philosophers - AN OVERVIEW
The greek philosophers - AN OVERVIEW
 
Greek Presentation (Gurrobat)
Greek Presentation (Gurrobat)Greek Presentation (Gurrobat)
Greek Presentation (Gurrobat)
 
Exeter · slides carnival
Exeter · slides carnivalExeter · slides carnival
Exeter · slides carnival
 

Destaque

Aristotles 090606082625
Aristotles 090606082625Aristotles 090606082625
Aristotles 090606082625Mohamad MADI
 
Feed the children
Feed the childrenFeed the children
Feed the childrenkanderson11
 
Wisdom About Work (Ecclesiastes 2:12-26)
Wisdom About Work (Ecclesiastes 2:12-26)Wisdom About Work (Ecclesiastes 2:12-26)
Wisdom About Work (Ecclesiastes 2:12-26)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
In His Time (Ecclesiastes 3:1-15)
In His Time (Ecclesiastes 3:1-15)In His Time (Ecclesiastes 3:1-15)
In His Time (Ecclesiastes 3:1-15)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
Wisdom in the Ups & Downs (Ecclesiastes 6:10–7:14)
Wisdom in the Ups & Downs (Ecclesiastes 6:10–7:14)Wisdom in the Ups & Downs (Ecclesiastes 6:10–7:14)
Wisdom in the Ups & Downs (Ecclesiastes 6:10–7:14)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
When Life is Unfair (Ecclesiastes 3:16-22)
When Life is Unfair (Ecclesiastes 3:16-22)When Life is Unfair (Ecclesiastes 3:16-22)
When Life is Unfair (Ecclesiastes 3:16-22)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
How to Honor God (Ecclesiastes 5:1-7)
How to Honor God (Ecclesiastes 5:1-7)How to Honor God (Ecclesiastes 5:1-7)
How to Honor God (Ecclesiastes 5:1-7)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
Submission & Joy (Ecclesiastes 8)
Submission & Joy (Ecclesiastes 8)Submission & Joy (Ecclesiastes 8)
Submission & Joy (Ecclesiastes 8)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
Workaholic Woes (Ecclesiastes 4)
Workaholic Woes (Ecclesiastes 4)Workaholic Woes (Ecclesiastes 4)
Workaholic Woes (Ecclesiastes 4)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
Revelation 4 Worthy of All Worship (Lewis)
Revelation 4 Worthy of All Worship (Lewis)Revelation 4 Worthy of All Worship (Lewis)
Revelation 4 Worthy of All Worship (Lewis)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
How to Get Rich (2 Cor. 8:1-15)
How to Get Rich (2 Cor. 8:1-15)How to Get Rich (2 Cor. 8:1-15)
How to Get Rich (2 Cor. 8:1-15)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
Benefits of Giving (2 Cor. 9:6-15)
Benefits of Giving (2 Cor. 9:6-15)Benefits of Giving (2 Cor. 9:6-15)
Benefits of Giving (2 Cor. 9:6-15)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
Revelation 2:8-11 Smyrna-Suffering Yet Steadfast
Revelation 2:8-11 Smyrna-Suffering Yet SteadfastRevelation 2:8-11 Smyrna-Suffering Yet Steadfast
Revelation 2:8-11 Smyrna-Suffering Yet SteadfastDr. Rick Griffith
 
Revelation 2:1-7 Ephesus-Learning to Love Again (Lewis Winkler)
Revelation 2:1-7 Ephesus-Learning to Love Again (Lewis Winkler)Revelation 2:1-7 Ephesus-Learning to Love Again (Lewis Winkler)
Revelation 2:1-7 Ephesus-Learning to Love Again (Lewis Winkler)Dr. Rick Griffith
 
Revelation 3:14-22 Laodicea Lukewarm
Revelation 3:14-22 Laodicea LukewarmRevelation 3:14-22 Laodicea Lukewarm
Revelation 3:14-22 Laodicea LukewarmDr. Rick Griffith
 
What to Do With an Uncertain Future (Ecclesiastes 11:1-6)
What to Do With an Uncertain Future (Ecclesiastes 11:1-6)What to Do With an Uncertain Future (Ecclesiastes 11:1-6)
What to Do With an Uncertain Future (Ecclesiastes 11:1-6)Dr. Rick Griffith
 

Destaque (19)

Food 3
Food 3Food 3
Food 3
 
Paper #1 ict in math
Paper #1 ict in mathPaper #1 ict in math
Paper #1 ict in math
 
Paper #1 ict in math
Paper #1 ict in mathPaper #1 ict in math
Paper #1 ict in math
 
Aristotles 090606082625
Aristotles 090606082625Aristotles 090606082625
Aristotles 090606082625
 
Feed the children
Feed the childrenFeed the children
Feed the children
 
Wisdom About Work (Ecclesiastes 2:12-26)
Wisdom About Work (Ecclesiastes 2:12-26)Wisdom About Work (Ecclesiastes 2:12-26)
Wisdom About Work (Ecclesiastes 2:12-26)
 
In His Time (Ecclesiastes 3:1-15)
In His Time (Ecclesiastes 3:1-15)In His Time (Ecclesiastes 3:1-15)
In His Time (Ecclesiastes 3:1-15)
 
Wisdom in the Ups & Downs (Ecclesiastes 6:10–7:14)
Wisdom in the Ups & Downs (Ecclesiastes 6:10–7:14)Wisdom in the Ups & Downs (Ecclesiastes 6:10–7:14)
Wisdom in the Ups & Downs (Ecclesiastes 6:10–7:14)
 
When Life is Unfair (Ecclesiastes 3:16-22)
When Life is Unfair (Ecclesiastes 3:16-22)When Life is Unfair (Ecclesiastes 3:16-22)
When Life is Unfair (Ecclesiastes 3:16-22)
 
How to Honor God (Ecclesiastes 5:1-7)
How to Honor God (Ecclesiastes 5:1-7)How to Honor God (Ecclesiastes 5:1-7)
How to Honor God (Ecclesiastes 5:1-7)
 
Submission & Joy (Ecclesiastes 8)
Submission & Joy (Ecclesiastes 8)Submission & Joy (Ecclesiastes 8)
Submission & Joy (Ecclesiastes 8)
 
Workaholic Woes (Ecclesiastes 4)
Workaholic Woes (Ecclesiastes 4)Workaholic Woes (Ecclesiastes 4)
Workaholic Woes (Ecclesiastes 4)
 
Revelation 4 Worthy of All Worship (Lewis)
Revelation 4 Worthy of All Worship (Lewis)Revelation 4 Worthy of All Worship (Lewis)
Revelation 4 Worthy of All Worship (Lewis)
 
How to Get Rich (2 Cor. 8:1-15)
How to Get Rich (2 Cor. 8:1-15)How to Get Rich (2 Cor. 8:1-15)
How to Get Rich (2 Cor. 8:1-15)
 
Benefits of Giving (2 Cor. 9:6-15)
Benefits of Giving (2 Cor. 9:6-15)Benefits of Giving (2 Cor. 9:6-15)
Benefits of Giving (2 Cor. 9:6-15)
 
Revelation 2:8-11 Smyrna-Suffering Yet Steadfast
Revelation 2:8-11 Smyrna-Suffering Yet SteadfastRevelation 2:8-11 Smyrna-Suffering Yet Steadfast
Revelation 2:8-11 Smyrna-Suffering Yet Steadfast
 
Revelation 2:1-7 Ephesus-Learning to Love Again (Lewis Winkler)
Revelation 2:1-7 Ephesus-Learning to Love Again (Lewis Winkler)Revelation 2:1-7 Ephesus-Learning to Love Again (Lewis Winkler)
Revelation 2:1-7 Ephesus-Learning to Love Again (Lewis Winkler)
 
Revelation 3:14-22 Laodicea Lukewarm
Revelation 3:14-22 Laodicea LukewarmRevelation 3:14-22 Laodicea Lukewarm
Revelation 3:14-22 Laodicea Lukewarm
 
What to Do With an Uncertain Future (Ecclesiastes 11:1-6)
What to Do With an Uncertain Future (Ecclesiastes 11:1-6)What to Do With an Uncertain Future (Ecclesiastes 11:1-6)
What to Do With an Uncertain Future (Ecclesiastes 11:1-6)
 

Semelhante a Aristotles (20)

Aristotle.docx
Aristotle.docxAristotle.docx
Aristotle.docx
 
Aristotle 1.docx
Aristotle 1.docxAristotle 1.docx
Aristotle 1.docx
 
The Nature of Biology
The Nature of BiologyThe Nature of Biology
The Nature of Biology
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
The athenian
The athenianThe athenian
The athenian
 
The three triumvirate PHILOSOPHY. rpc
The three triumvirate PHILOSOPHY. rpcThe three triumvirate PHILOSOPHY. rpc
The three triumvirate PHILOSOPHY. rpc
 
CONTRIBUTIONS BY ARISTOTLE PRESENTATION
CONTRIBUTIONS  BY ARISTOTLE PRESENTATIONCONTRIBUTIONS  BY ARISTOTLE PRESENTATION
CONTRIBUTIONS BY ARISTOTLE PRESENTATION
 
Greek and hellenistic mathematics
Greek and hellenistic mathematicsGreek and hellenistic mathematics
Greek and hellenistic mathematics
 
Philo ppt
Philo pptPhilo ppt
Philo ppt
 
Pre socratic
Pre socraticPre socratic
Pre socratic
 
My Report (Aristotle)
My Report (Aristotle)My Report (Aristotle)
My Report (Aristotle)
 
ALONG ARISTOTLE.docx
ALONG ARISTOTLE.docxALONG ARISTOTLE.docx
ALONG ARISTOTLE.docx
 
Greece
GreeceGreece
Greece
 
Aristotle's Poetics
Aristotle's PoeticsAristotle's Poetics
Aristotle's Poetics
 
The three triumvirate. rpc
The three triumvirate. rpcThe three triumvirate. rpc
The three triumvirate. rpc
 
Great philosophers
Great philosophersGreat philosophers
Great philosophers
 
Aristotle
AristotleAristotle
Aristotle
 
Plato
PlatoPlato
Plato
 
Hellenic Culture
Hellenic CultureHellenic Culture
Hellenic Culture
 
Historical Development of Logic
Historical Development of LogicHistorical Development of Logic
Historical Development of Logic
 

Último

Design For Accessibility: Getting it right from the start
Design For Accessibility: Getting it right from the startDesign For Accessibility: Getting it right from the start
Design For Accessibility: Getting it right from the startQuintin Balsdon
 
Moment Distribution Method For Btech Civil
Moment Distribution Method For Btech CivilMoment Distribution Method For Btech Civil
Moment Distribution Method For Btech CivilVinayVitekari
 
Thermal Engineering -unit - III & IV.ppt
Thermal Engineering -unit - III & IV.pptThermal Engineering -unit - III & IV.ppt
Thermal Engineering -unit - III & IV.pptDineshKumar4165
 
AIRCANVAS[1].pdf mini project for btech students
AIRCANVAS[1].pdf mini project for btech studentsAIRCANVAS[1].pdf mini project for btech students
AIRCANVAS[1].pdf mini project for btech studentsvanyagupta248
 
GEAR TRAIN- BASIC CONCEPTS AND WORKING PRINCIPLE
GEAR TRAIN- BASIC CONCEPTS AND WORKING PRINCIPLEGEAR TRAIN- BASIC CONCEPTS AND WORKING PRINCIPLE
GEAR TRAIN- BASIC CONCEPTS AND WORKING PRINCIPLEselvakumar948
 
Employee leave management system project.
Employee leave management system project.Employee leave management system project.
Employee leave management system project.Kamal Acharya
 
HOA1&2 - Module 3 - PREHISTORCI ARCHITECTURE OF KERALA.pptx
HOA1&2 - Module 3 - PREHISTORCI ARCHITECTURE OF KERALA.pptxHOA1&2 - Module 3 - PREHISTORCI ARCHITECTURE OF KERALA.pptx
HOA1&2 - Module 3 - PREHISTORCI ARCHITECTURE OF KERALA.pptxSCMS School of Architecture
 
1_Introduction + EAM Vocabulary + how to navigate in EAM.pdf
1_Introduction + EAM Vocabulary + how to navigate in EAM.pdf1_Introduction + EAM Vocabulary + how to navigate in EAM.pdf
1_Introduction + EAM Vocabulary + how to navigate in EAM.pdfAldoGarca30
 
PE 459 LECTURE 2- natural gas basic concepts and properties
PE 459 LECTURE 2- natural gas basic concepts and propertiesPE 459 LECTURE 2- natural gas basic concepts and properties
PE 459 LECTURE 2- natural gas basic concepts and propertiessarkmank1
 
Thermal Engineering Unit - I & II . ppt
Thermal Engineering  Unit - I & II . pptThermal Engineering  Unit - I & II . ppt
Thermal Engineering Unit - I & II . pptDineshKumar4165
 
data_management_and _data_science_cheat_sheet.pdf
data_management_and _data_science_cheat_sheet.pdfdata_management_and _data_science_cheat_sheet.pdf
data_management_and _data_science_cheat_sheet.pdfJiananWang21
 
A Study of Urban Area Plan for Pabna Municipality
A Study of Urban Area Plan for Pabna MunicipalityA Study of Urban Area Plan for Pabna Municipality
A Study of Urban Area Plan for Pabna MunicipalityMorshed Ahmed Rahath
 
Computer Lecture 01.pptxIntroduction to Computers
Computer Lecture 01.pptxIntroduction to ComputersComputer Lecture 01.pptxIntroduction to Computers
Computer Lecture 01.pptxIntroduction to ComputersMairaAshraf6
 
Computer Networks Basics of Network Devices
Computer Networks  Basics of Network DevicesComputer Networks  Basics of Network Devices
Computer Networks Basics of Network DevicesChandrakantDivate1
 
Wadi Rum luxhotel lodge Analysis case study.pptx
Wadi Rum luxhotel lodge Analysis case study.pptxWadi Rum luxhotel lodge Analysis case study.pptx
Wadi Rum luxhotel lodge Analysis case study.pptxNadaHaitham1
 
Hostel management system project report..pdf
Hostel management system project report..pdfHostel management system project report..pdf
Hostel management system project report..pdfKamal Acharya
 
XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXssuser89054b
 
Standard vs Custom Battery Packs - Decoding the Power Play
Standard vs Custom Battery Packs - Decoding the Power PlayStandard vs Custom Battery Packs - Decoding the Power Play
Standard vs Custom Battery Packs - Decoding the Power PlayEpec Engineered Technologies
 

Último (20)

Design For Accessibility: Getting it right from the start
Design For Accessibility: Getting it right from the startDesign For Accessibility: Getting it right from the start
Design For Accessibility: Getting it right from the start
 
Moment Distribution Method For Btech Civil
Moment Distribution Method For Btech CivilMoment Distribution Method For Btech Civil
Moment Distribution Method For Btech Civil
 
Thermal Engineering -unit - III & IV.ppt
Thermal Engineering -unit - III & IV.pptThermal Engineering -unit - III & IV.ppt
Thermal Engineering -unit - III & IV.ppt
 
AIRCANVAS[1].pdf mini project for btech students
AIRCANVAS[1].pdf mini project for btech studentsAIRCANVAS[1].pdf mini project for btech students
AIRCANVAS[1].pdf mini project for btech students
 
GEAR TRAIN- BASIC CONCEPTS AND WORKING PRINCIPLE
GEAR TRAIN- BASIC CONCEPTS AND WORKING PRINCIPLEGEAR TRAIN- BASIC CONCEPTS AND WORKING PRINCIPLE
GEAR TRAIN- BASIC CONCEPTS AND WORKING PRINCIPLE
 
Employee leave management system project.
Employee leave management system project.Employee leave management system project.
Employee leave management system project.
 
HOA1&2 - Module 3 - PREHISTORCI ARCHITECTURE OF KERALA.pptx
HOA1&2 - Module 3 - PREHISTORCI ARCHITECTURE OF KERALA.pptxHOA1&2 - Module 3 - PREHISTORCI ARCHITECTURE OF KERALA.pptx
HOA1&2 - Module 3 - PREHISTORCI ARCHITECTURE OF KERALA.pptx
 
1_Introduction + EAM Vocabulary + how to navigate in EAM.pdf
1_Introduction + EAM Vocabulary + how to navigate in EAM.pdf1_Introduction + EAM Vocabulary + how to navigate in EAM.pdf
1_Introduction + EAM Vocabulary + how to navigate in EAM.pdf
 
PE 459 LECTURE 2- natural gas basic concepts and properties
PE 459 LECTURE 2- natural gas basic concepts and propertiesPE 459 LECTURE 2- natural gas basic concepts and properties
PE 459 LECTURE 2- natural gas basic concepts and properties
 
Thermal Engineering Unit - I & II . ppt
Thermal Engineering  Unit - I & II . pptThermal Engineering  Unit - I & II . ppt
Thermal Engineering Unit - I & II . ppt
 
FEA Based Level 3 Assessment of Deformed Tanks with Fluid Induced Loads
FEA Based Level 3 Assessment of Deformed Tanks with Fluid Induced LoadsFEA Based Level 3 Assessment of Deformed Tanks with Fluid Induced Loads
FEA Based Level 3 Assessment of Deformed Tanks with Fluid Induced Loads
 
data_management_and _data_science_cheat_sheet.pdf
data_management_and _data_science_cheat_sheet.pdfdata_management_and _data_science_cheat_sheet.pdf
data_management_and _data_science_cheat_sheet.pdf
 
A Study of Urban Area Plan for Pabna Municipality
A Study of Urban Area Plan for Pabna MunicipalityA Study of Urban Area Plan for Pabna Municipality
A Study of Urban Area Plan for Pabna Municipality
 
Computer Lecture 01.pptxIntroduction to Computers
Computer Lecture 01.pptxIntroduction to ComputersComputer Lecture 01.pptxIntroduction to Computers
Computer Lecture 01.pptxIntroduction to Computers
 
Computer Networks Basics of Network Devices
Computer Networks  Basics of Network DevicesComputer Networks  Basics of Network Devices
Computer Networks Basics of Network Devices
 
Integrated Test Rig For HTFE-25 - Neometrix
Integrated Test Rig For HTFE-25 - NeometrixIntegrated Test Rig For HTFE-25 - Neometrix
Integrated Test Rig For HTFE-25 - Neometrix
 
Wadi Rum luxhotel lodge Analysis case study.pptx
Wadi Rum luxhotel lodge Analysis case study.pptxWadi Rum luxhotel lodge Analysis case study.pptx
Wadi Rum luxhotel lodge Analysis case study.pptx
 
Hostel management system project report..pdf
Hostel management system project report..pdfHostel management system project report..pdf
Hostel management system project report..pdf
 
XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX
 
Standard vs Custom Battery Packs - Decoding the Power Play
Standard vs Custom Battery Packs - Decoding the Power PlayStandard vs Custom Battery Packs - Decoding the Power Play
Standard vs Custom Battery Packs - Decoding the Power Play
 

Aristotles

  • 1. Aristotle (Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης Aristotélēs) (384 BC – 322 BC) was a Greek philosopher, a student of Plato and teacher of Alexander the Great. He wrote on many subjects, including physics, metaphysics, poetry, theater, music, logic, rhetoric, politics, government, ethics, biology and zoology. Together with Plato and Socrates (Plato's teacher), Aristotle is one of the most important founding figures in Western philosophy. He was the first to create a comprehensive system of Western philosophy, encompassing morality and aesthetics, logic and science, politics and metaphysics. Aristotle's views on the physical sciences profoundly shaped medieval scholarship, and their influence extended well into the Renaissance, although they were ultimately replaced by modern physics. In the biological sciences, some of his observations were only confirmed to be accurate in the nineteenth century. His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, which were incorporated in the late nineteenth century into modern formal logic. In metaphysics, Aristotelianism had a profound influence on philosophical and theological thinking in the Islamic and Jewish traditions in the Middle Ages, and it continues to influence Christian theology, especially Eastern Orthodox theology, and the scholastic tradition of the Roman Catholic Church. All aspects of Aristotle's philosophy continue to be the object of active academic study today. Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues (Cicero described his literary style as "a river of gold"), it is thought that the majority of his writings are now lost and only about one third of the original works have survived.[1] Contents [hide] · 1 Life · 2 Logic o 2.1 History o 2.2 Analytics and the Organon · 3 Aristotle's scientific method · 4 Physics o 4.1 The five elements o 4.2 Causality, The Four Causes o 4.3 Chance and spontaneity · 5 Metaphysics o 5.1 Substance, potentiality and actuality o 5.2 Universals and particulars · 6 Biology and medicine o 6.1 Empirical research program o 6.2 Classification of living things o 6.3 Theory of biological forms and souls o 6.4 Aristotle's successor: Theophrastus o 6.5 Influence on Hellenistic medicine · 7 Practical Philosophy o 7.1 Ethics
  • 2. o 7.2 Politics o 7.3 Rhetoric and poetics · 8 The loss of his works · 9 Legacy · 10 List of Aristotle's works · 11 Notes and References · 12 Further reading · 13 See also · 14 External links o 14.1 Collections of Aristotle's works o 14.2 Articles on Aristotle Life Aristotle was born in Stageira, Chalcidice, in 384 BC, about 55 km east of modern-day Thessaloniki.[2] His father, Nicomachus was the personal physician to King Amyntas of Macedon. Aristotle was trained and educated as a member of the aristocracy. At about the age of eighteen, he went to Athens to continue his education at Plato's Academy. Aristotle remained at the academy for nearly twenty years, not leaving until after Plato's death in 347 BC. He then traveled with Xenocrates to the court of his friend Hermias of Atarneus in Asia Minor. While in Asia, Aristotle traveled with Theophrastus to the island of Lesbos, where together they researched the botany and zoology of the island. Aristotle married Hermias's adoptive daughter (or niece) Pythias. She bore him a daughter, whom they named Pythias. Soon after Hermias' death, Aristotle was invited by Philip of Macedon to become tutor to Alexander the Great in 343 B.C.[3] During his time as the head of Macedon's royal academy, Aristotle gave lessons not only to Alexander, but also to two other future kings: Ptolemy and Cassander. In his Politics, Aristotle states that only one thing could justify monarchy, and that was if the virtue of the king and his family were greater than the virtue of the rest of the citizens put together. Tactfully, he included the young prince and his father in that category. Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern conquest, and his attitude towards Persia was unabashedly ethnocentric. In one famous example, he counsels Alexander to be 'a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians, to look after the former as after friends and relatives, and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants'.[4] Near the end of Alexander's life he began to suspect plots, and threatened Aristotle in letters. Aristotle had made no secret of his contempt for Alexander's pretense of divinity, and the king had executed Aristotle's grand-nephew Callisthenes as a traitor. A widespread tradition in antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in Alexander's death, but there is little evidence for this.[5] By 335 BC he had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the Lyceum. Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years. While in Athens, his wife Pythias died, and Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stageira, who bore him a son
  • 3. whom he named after his father, Nicomachus. According to the Suda, he also had an eromenos, Palaephatus of Abydus.[6] It is during this period in Athens from 335 B.C. to 323 B.C. when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his works.[7] Aristotle wrote many dialogues, only fragments of which survived. The works that have survived are in treatise form and were not, for the most part, intended for widespread publication, as they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students. His most important treatises include Physics, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics, Politics, De Anima (On the Soul) and Poetics. Aristotle not only studied almost every subject possible at the time, but made significant contributions to most of them. In physical science, Aristotle studied anatomy, astronomy, economics, embryology, geography, geology, meteorology, physics and zoology. In philosophy, he wrote on aesthetics, ethics, government, metaphysics, politics, psychology, rhetoric and theology. He also studied education, foreign customs, literature and poetry. His combined works constitute a virtual encyclopedia of Greek knowledge. It has been suggested that Aristotle was probably the last person to know everything there was to be known in his own time.[8] Upon Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens once again flared. Eurymedon the hierophant denounced Aristotle for not holding the gods in honor. Aristotle fled the city to his mother's family estate in Chalcis, explaining, "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy,"[9] a reference to Athens's prior trial and execution of Socrates. However, he died in Euboea of natural causes within the year (in 322 BC). Aristotle named chief executor his student Antipater and left a will in which he asked to be buried next to his wife.[10] Logic Main article: Term logic For more details on this topic, see Non-Aristotelian logic. Aristotle's conception of logic was the dominant form of logic until 19th century advances in mathematical logic. Kant stated in the Critique of Pure Reason that Aristotle's theory of logic completely accounted for the core of deductive inference. History Aristotle "says that 'on the subject of reasoning' he 'had nothing else on an earlier date to speak of'".[11] However, Plato reports that syntax was devised before him, by Prodicus of Ceos, who was concerned by the correct use of words. Logic seems to have emerged from dialectics; the earlier philosophers made frequent use of concepts like reductio ad absurdum in their discussions, but never truly understood the logical implications. Even Plato had difficulties with logic; although he had a reasonable conception of a deduction system, he could never actually construct one and relied instead on his dialectic.[12] Plato believed that deduction would simply follow from premises, hence he focused on maintaining solid premises so that the conclusion would logically follow. Consequently, Plato realized that a method for obtaining conclusions
  • 4. would be most beneficial. He never succeeded in devising such a method, but his best attempt was published in his book Sophist, where he introduced his division method.[13] Analytics and the Organon Main article: Organon What we today call Aristotelian logic, Aristotle himself would have labeled "analytics". The term "logic" he reserved to mean dialectics. Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, since it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into six books in about the early 1st century AD: 1. Categories 2. On Interpretation 3. Prior Analytics 4. Posterior Analytics 5. Topics 6. On Sophistical Refutations The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the Categories, to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the Analytics) and dialectics (in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations). There is one volume of Aristotle's concerning logic not found in the Organon, namely the fourth book of Metaphysics.. [12] Aristotle's scientific method Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of The School of Athens, a fresco by Raphael. Aristotle gestures to the earth, representing his belief in knowledge through empirical observation and experience, while holding a copy of his Nicomachean Ethics in his hand, whilst Plato gestures to the heavens, representing his belief in The Forms. For more details on this topic, see Aristotle's theory of universals.
  • 5. Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the universal. Aristotle, however, found the universal in particular things, which he called the essence of things, while Plato finds that the universal exists apart from particular things, and is related to them as their prototype or exemplar. For Aristotle, therefore, philosophic method implies the ascent from the study of particular phenomena to the knowledge of essences, while for Plato philosophic method means the descent from a knowledge of universal Forms (or ideas) to a contemplation of particular imitations of these. For Aristotle, "form" still refers to the unconditional basis of phenomena but is "instantiated" in a particular substance (see Universals and particulars, below). In a certain sense, Aristotle's method is both inductive and deductive, while Plato's is essentially deductive from a priori principles.[14] In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, biology and other natural sciences. In modern times, the scope of philosophy has become limited to more generic or abstract inquiries, such as ethics and metaphysics, in which logic plays a major role. Today's philosophy tends to exclude empirical study of the natural world by means of the scientific method. In contrast, Aristotle's philosophical endeavors encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. In the larger sense of the word, Aristotle makes philosophy coextensive with reasoning, which he also would describe as "science". Note, however, that his use of the term science carries a different meaning than that covered by the term "scientific method". For Aristotle, "all science (dianoia) is either practical, poetical or theoretical" (Metaphysics 1025b25). By practical science, he means ethics and politics; by poetical science, he means the study of poetry and the other fine arts; by theoretical science, he means physics, mathematics and metaphysics. If logic (or "analytics") is regarded as a study preliminary to philosophy, the divisions of Aristotelian philosophy would consist of: (1) Logic; (2) Theoretical Philosophy, including Metaphysics, Physics, Mathematics, (3) Practical Philosophy and (4) Poetical Philosophy. In the period between his two stays in Athens, between his times at the Academy and the Lyceum, Aristotle conducted most of the scientific thinking and research for which he is renowned today. In fact, most of Aristotle's life was devoted to the study of the objects of natural science. Aristotle's metaphysics contains observations on the nature of numbers but he made no original contributions to mathematics. He did, however, perform original research in the natural sciences, e.g., botany, zoology, physics, astronomy, chemistry, meteorology, and several other sciences. Aristotle's writings on science are largely qualitative, as opposed to quantitative. Beginning in the sixteenth century, scientists began applying mathematics to the physical sciences, and Aristotle's work in this area was deemed hopelessly inadequate. His failings were largely due to the absence of concepts like mass, velocity, force and temperature. He had a conception of speed and temperature, but no quantitative understanding of them, which was partly due to the absence of basic experimental devices, like clocks and thermometers.
  • 6. A green and red Perseid meteor is striking the sky just below the Milky Way in August 2007. His writings provide an account of many scientific observations, a mixture of precocious accuracy and curious errors. For example, in his History of Animals he claimed that human males have more teeth than females.[15] In a similar vein, John Philoponus, and later Galileo, showed by simple experiments that Aristotle's theory that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect.[16] On the other hand, Aristotle refuted Democritus's claim that the Milky Way was made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out (correctly, even if such reasoning was bound to be dismissed for a long time) that, given "current astronomical demonstrations" that "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then...the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them."[17] In places, Aristotle goes too far in deriving 'laws of the universe' from simple observation and over-stretched reason. Today's scientific method assumes that such thinking without sufficient facts is ineffective, and that discerning the validity of one's hypothesis requires far more rigorous experimentation than that which Aristotle used to support his laws. Aristotle also had some scientific blind spots. He posited a geocentric cosmology that we may discern in selections of the Metaphysics, which was widely accepted up until the 1500s. From the 3rd century to the 1500s, the dominant view held that the Earth was the center of the universe (geocentrism). Since he was perhaps the philosopher most respected by European thinkers during and after the Renaissance, these thinkers often took Aristotle's erroneous positions as given, which held back science in this epoch.[18] However, Aristotle's scientific shortcomings should not mislead one into forgetting his great advances in the many scientific fields. For instance, he founded logic as a formal science and created foundations to biology that were not superseded for two millennia. Moreover, he introduced the fundamental notion that nature is composed of things that change and that studying such changes can provide useful knowledge of underlying constants. Physics Main article: Physics (Aristotle) The five elements
  • 7. Main article: Classical element · Fire , which is hot and dry. · Earth , which is cold and dry. · Air , which is hot and wet. · Water , which is cold and wet. · Aether , which is the divine substance that makes up the heavenly spheres and heavenly bodies (stars and planets). Each of the four earthly elements has its natural place; the earth at the centre of the universe, then water, then air, then fire. When they are out of their natural place they have natural motion, requiring no external cause, which is towards that place; so bodies sink in water, air bubbles up, rain falls, flame rises in air. The heavenly element has perpetual circular motion. Causality, The Four Causes Main article: Four causes · The material cause is that from which a thing comes into existence as from its part, constituents, substratum or materials. This reduces the explanation of causes to the parts (factors, elements, constituents, ingredients) forming the whole (system, structure, compound, complex, composite, or combination), a relationship known as the part-whole causation. Simply put it is the influence of the material substances on the event. So imagine two dominos, the first of which is lighter. The first is knocked over into the second but does not have enough power to knock it over, this is Material cause. · The formal cause tells us what a thing is, that any thing is determined by the definition, form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis or archetype. It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental principles or general laws, as the whole (i.e., macrostructure) is the cause of its parts, a relationship known as the whole-part causation. Plainly put it is the influence of the form (essence) of the things on the event. So take the two dominos again except this time the second is shaped to prevent it from falling *eg. triangular.* this is formal cause. · The efficient cause is that from which the change or the ending of the change first starts. It identifies 'what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is changed' and so suggests all sorts of agents, nonliving or living, acting as the sources of change or movement or rest. Representing the current understanding of causality as the relation of cause and effect, this covers the modern definitions of "cause" as either the agent or agency or particular events or states of affairs. More simply again that which immediately sets the thing in motion. So take the two dominos this time of equal weighting, the first is knocked over causing the second also to fall over. This is effectively efficient cause. · The final cause is that for the sake of which a thing exists or is done, including both purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. The final cause or telos is the purpose or end that something is supposed to serve, or it is that from which and that to which the change is. This also covers modern ideas of mental causation involving such psychological causes as volition, need, motivation, or motives, rational, irrational, ethical, all that gives purpose to behavior.
  • 8. Additionally, things can be causes of one another, causing each other reciprocally, as hard work causes fitness and vice versa, although not in the same way or function, the one is as the beginning of change, the other as the goal. (Thus Aristotle first suggested a reciprocal or circular causality as a relation of mutual dependence or influence of cause upon effect). Moreover, Aristotle indicated that the same thing can be the cause of contrary effects; its presence and absence may result in different outcomes. Simply it is the goal or purpose that brings about an event (not necessarily a mental goal). Taking our two dominos, it requires someone to intentionally knock the dominos over as they cannot fall themselves. Aristotle marked two modes of causation: proper (prior) causation and accidental (chance) causation. All causes, proper and incidental, can be spoken as potential or as actual, particular or generic. The same language refers to the effects of causes, so that generic effects assigned to generic causes, particular effects to particular causes, operating causes to actual effects. Essentially, causality does not suggest a temporal relation between the cause and the effect. All further investigations of causality will consist of imposing the favorite hierarchies on the order causes, such as final > efficient > material > formal (Thomas Aquinas), or of restricting all causality to the material and efficient causes or to the efficient causality (deterministic or chance) or just to regular sequences and correlations of natural phenomena (the natural sciences describing how things happen instead of explaining the whys and wherefores). Chance and spontaneity Spontaneity and chance are causes of effects. Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of accidental things. It is "from what is spontaneous" (but note that what is spontaneous does not come from chance). For a better understanding of Aristotle's conception of "chance" it might be better to think of "coincidence": Something takes place by chance if a person sets out with the intent of having one thing take place, but with the result of another thing (not intended) taking place. For example: A person seeks donations. That person may find another person willing to donate a substantial sum. However, if the person seeking the donations met the person donating, not for the purpose of collecting donations, but for some other purpose, Aristotle would call the collecting of the donation by that particular donator a result of chance. It must be unusual that something happens by chance. In other words, if something happens all or most of the time, we cannot say that it is by chance. There is also more specific kind of chance, which Aristotle names "luck", that can only apply to human beings, since it is in the sphere of moral actions. According to Aristotle, luck must involve choice (and thus deliberation), and only humans are capable of deliberation and choice. "What is not capable of action cannot do anything by chance".[19] Metaphysics Main article: Metaphysics (Aristotle)
  • 9. Aristotle defines metaphysics as "the knowledge of immaterial being," or of "being in the highest degree of abstraction." He refers to metaphysics as "first philosophy", as well as "the theologic science." Substance, potentiality and actuality Aristotle examines the concept of substance and essence (ousia) in his Metaphysics, Book VII and he concludes that a particular substance is a combination of both matter and form. As he proceeds to the book VIII, he concludes that the matter of the substance is the substratum or the stuff of which it is composed, e.g. the matter of the house are the bricks, stones, timbers etc., or whatever constitutes the potential house. While the form of the substance, is the actual house, namely 'covering for bodies and chattels' or any other differentia (see also predicables). The formula that gives the components is the account of the matter, and the formula that gives the differentia is the account of the form.[20] With regard to the change (kinesis) and its causes now, as he defines in his Physics and On Generation and Corruption 319b-320a, he distinguishes the coming to be from: 1) growth and diminution, which is change in quantity; 2) locomotion, which is change in space; and 3) alteration, which is change in quality. The coming to be is a change where nothing persists of which the resultant is a property. In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (dynamis) and actuality (entelecheia) in association with the matter and the form. Referring to potentiality, this is what a thing is capable of doing, or being acted upon, if it is not prevented by something else. For example, the seed of a plant in the soil is potentially (dynamei) plant, and if is not prevented by something, it will become a plant. Potentially beings can either 'act' (poiein) or 'be acted upon' (paschein), which can be either innate or learned. For example, the eyes possess the potentiality of sight (innate - being acted upon), while the capability of playing the flute can be possessed by learning (exercise - acting). Actuality is the fulfillment of the end of the potentiality. Because the end (telos) is the principle of every change, and for the sake of the end exists potentiality, therefore actuality is the end. Referring then to our previous example, we could say that actuality is when the seed of the plant becomes a plant. " For that for the sake of which a thing is, is its principle, and the becoming is for the sake of the end; and the actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this that the potentiality is acquired. For animals do not see in order that they may have sight, but they have sight that they may see."[21] In conclusion, the matter of the house is its potentiality and the form is its actuality. The formal cause (aitia) then of that change from potential to actual house, is the reason (logos) of the house builder and the final cause is the end, namely the house itself. Then Aristotle proceeds and concludes that the actuality is prior to potentiality in formula, in time and in substantiality.
  • 10. With this definition of the particular substance (i.e., matter and form), Aristotle tries to solve the problem of the unity of the beings, e.g., what is that makes the man one? Since, according to Plato there are two Ideas: animal and biped, how then is man a unity? However, according to Aristotle, the potential being (matter) and the actual one (form) are one and the same thing.[22] Universals and particulars Main article: Aristotle's theory of universals Aristotle's predecessor, Plato, argued that all things have a universal form, which could be either a property, or a relation to other things. When we look at an apple, for example, we see an apple, and we can also analyze a form of an apple. In this distinction, there is a particular apple and a universal form of an apple. Moreover, we can place an apple next to a book, so that we can speak of both the book and apple as being next to each other. Plato argued that there are some universal forms that are not a part of particular things. For example, it is possible that there is no particular good in existence, but "good" is still a proper universal form. Bertrand Russell is a contemporary philosopher that agreed with Plato on the existence of "uninstantiated universals". Aristotle disagreed with Plato on this point, arguing that all universals are instantiated. Aristotle argued that there are no universals that are unattached to existing things. According to Aristotle, if a universal exists, either as a particular or a relation, then there must have been, must be currently, or must be in the future, something on which the universal can be predicated. Consequently, according to Aristotle, if it is not the case that some universal can be predicated to an object that exists at some period of time, then it does not exist. One way for contemporary philosophers to justify this position is by asserting the eleatic principle. In addition, Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals. As Plato spoke of the world of the forms, a location where all universal forms subsist, Aristotle maintained that universals exist within each thing on which each universal is predicated. So, according to Aristotle, the form of apple exists within each apple, rather than in the world of the forms. Biology and medicine In Aristotelian science, most especially in biology, things he saw himself have stood the test of time better than his retelling of the reports of others, which contain error and superstition. He dissected animals, but not humans and his ideas on how the human body works have been almost entirely superseded. Empirical research program
  • 11. Octopus swimming Torpedo fuscomaculata Aristotle is the earliest natural historian whose work has survived in some detail. Aristotle certainly did research on the natural history of Lesbos, and the surrounding seas and neighbouring areas. The works that reflect this research, such as History of Animals, Generation of Animals, and Parts of Animals, contain some observations and interpretations, along with sundry myths and mistakes. The most striking passages are about the sea-life visible from observation on Lesbos and available from the catches of fishermen. His observations on catfish, electric fish (Torpedo) and angler-fish are detailed, as is his writing on cephalopods, namely, Octopus, Sepia (cuttlefish) and the paper nautilus (Argonauta argo). His description of the hectocotyl arm was about two thousand years ahead of its time, and widely disbelieved until its rediscovery in the nineteenth century. He separated the aquatic mammals from fish, and knew that sharks and rays were part of the group he called Selachē (selachians).[23] Leopard shark Another good example of his methods comes from the Generation of Animals in which Aristotle describes breaking open fertilized chicken eggs at intervals to observe when visible organs were generated. He gave accurate descriptions of ruminants' four-chambered fore-stomachs, and of the ovoviviparous embryological development of the hound shark Mustelus mustelus.[24] Classification of living things
  • 12. Aristotle's classification of living things contains some elements which still existed in the nineteenth century. What the modern zoologist would call vertebrates and invertebrates, Aristotle called 'animals with blood' and 'animals without blood' (he was not to know that complex invertebrates do make use of haemoglobin, but of a different kind from vertebrates). Animals with blood were divided into live-bearing (humans and mammals), and egg-bearing (birds and fish). Invertebrates ('animals without blood') are insects, crustacea (divided into non-shelled – cephalopods – and shelled) and testacea (molluscs). In some respects, this incomplete classification is better than that of Linnaeus, who crowded the invertebrata together into two groups, Insecta and Vermes (worms). For Charles Singer, "Nothing is more remarkable than [Aristotle's] efforts to [exhibit] the relationships of living things as a scala naturae"[23] Aristotle's History of Animals classified organisms in relation to a hierarchical "Ladder of Life" (scala naturae), placing them according to complexity of structure and function so that higher organisms showed greater vitality and ability to move.[25] Aristotle believed that intellectual purposes, i.e., formal causes, guided all natural processes. Such a teleological view gave Aristotle cause to justify his observed data as an expression of formal design. Noting that "no animal has, at the same time, both tusks and horns," and "a single-hooved animal with two horns I have never seen," Aristotle suggested that Nature, giving no animal both horns and tusks, was staving off vanity, and giving creatures faculties only to such a degree as they are necessary. Noting that ruminants had a multiple stomachs and weak teeth, he supposed the first was to compensate for the latter, with Nature trying to preserve a type of balance.[26] In a similar fashion, Aristotle believed that creatures were arranged in a graded scale of perfection rising from plants on up to man, the scala naturae or Great Chain of Being.[27] His system had eleven grades, arranged according "to the degree to which they are infected with potentiality", expressed in their form at birth. The highest animals laid warm and wet creatures alive, the lowest bore theirs cold, dry, and in thick eggs. Theory of biological forms and souls Aristotle also held that the level of a creature's perfection was reflected in its form, but not preordained by that form. Ideas like this, and his ideas about souls, are not regarded as science at all in modern times. He placed emphasis on the type(s) of soul an organism possessed, asserting that plants possess a vegetative soul, responsible for reproduction and growth, animals a vegetative and a sensitive soul, responsible for mobility and sensation, and humans a vegetative, a sensitive, and a rational soul, capable of thought and reflection.[28] Aristotle, in contrast to earlier philosophers, but in accordance with the Egyptians, placed the rational soul in the heart, rather than the brain.[29] Notable is Aristotle's division of sensation and thought, which generally went against previous philosophers, with the exception of Alcmaeon.[30]
  • 13. His analysis of procreation is frequently criticized on the grounds that it presupposes an active, ensouling masculine element bringing life to an inert, passive, lumpen female element; it is on these grounds that Aristotle is considered by some feminist critics to have been a misogynist.[31] Aristotle's successor: Theophrastus Frontispiece to a 1644 version of the expanded and illustrated edition of Historia Plantarum (ca. 1200), which was originally written around 200 BC Main articles: Theophrastus and Historia Plantarum Aristotle's successor at the Lyceum, Theophrastus, wrote a series of books on botany—the History of Plants—which survived as the most important contribution of antiquity to botany, even into the Middle Ages. Many of Theophrastus' names survive into modern times, such as carpos for fruit, and pericarpion for seed vessel. Rather than focus on formal causes, as Aristotle did, Theophrastus suggested a mechanistic scheme, drawing analogies between natural and artificial processes, and relying on Aristotle's concept of the efficient cause. Theophrastus also recognized the role of sex in the reproduction of some higher plants, though this last discovery was lost in later ages.[32] Influence on Hellenistic medicine For more details on this topic, see Medicine in ancient Greece. After Theophrastus, the Lyceum failed to produce any original work. Though interest in Aristotle's ideas survived, they were generally taken unquestioningly.[33] It is not until the age of Alexandria under the Ptolemies that advances in biology can be again found. The first medical teacher at Alexandria Herophilus of Chalcedon, corrected Aristotle, placing intelligence in the brain, and connected the nervous system to motion and sensation. Herophilus also distinguished between veins and arteries, noting that the latter pulse while the former do not. [34] Though a few ancient atomists such as Lucretius challenged the teleological viewpoint of Aristotelian ideas about life, teleology (and after the rise of Christianity, natural theology) would remain central to biological thought essentially until the 18th and 19th centuries. Ernst Mayr
  • 14. claimed that there was "nothing of any real consequence in biology after Lucretius and Galen until the Renaissance."[35] Aristotle's ideas of natural history and medicine survived, but they were generally taken unquestioningly.[36] Practical Philosophy Ethics Main article: Aristotelian ethics Aristotle considered ethics to be a practical science, i.e., one mastered by doing rather than merely reasoning. Further, Aristotle believed that ethical knowledge is not certain knowledge (such as metaphysics or epistemology) but is general knowledge. He wrote several treatises on ethics, including most notably, Nichomachean Ethics, in which he outlines what is commonly called virtue ethics. Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function of a thing. An eye is only a good eye in so much as it can see, because the proper function of an eye is sight. Aristotle reasoned that man must have a function uncommon to anything else, and that this function must be an activity of the soul. Aristotle identified the best activity of the soul as eudaimonia: a happiness or joy that pervades the good life. Aristotle taught that to achieve the good life, one must live a balanced life and avoid excess. This balance, he taught, varies among different persons and situations, and exists as a golden mean between two vices - one an excess and one a deficiency. Politics Main article: Politics (Aristotle) In addition to his works on ethics, which address the individual, Aristotle addressed the city in his work titled Politics. Aristotle's conception of the city is organic, and he is considered one of the first to conceive of the city in this manner.[37] Aristotle considered the city to be a natural community. Moreover, he considered the city to be prior to the family which in turn is prior to the individual, i.e., last in the order of becoming, but first in the order of being . He is also famous for his statement that "man is by nature a political animal." Aristotle conceived of politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine, and as a collection of parts none of which can exist without the others. It should be noted that the modern understanding of a political community is that of the state. However, the state was foreign to Aristotle. He referred to political communities as cities. Aristotle understood a city as a political "partnership" and not one of a social contract (or compact) or a political community as understood by Niccolò Machiavelli. Subsequently, a city is created not to avoid injustice or for economic stability , but rather to live a good life: "The political partnership must be regarded, therefore, as being for the sake of noble actions, not for the sake of living together" . This can be distinguished from the social contract theory which individuals leave the state of nature because of "fear of violent death" or its "inconveniences."[38]
  • 15. Rhetoric and poetics Main articles: Rhetoric (Aristotle) and Poetics (Aristotle) Aristotle considered epic poetry, tragedy, comedy, dithyrambic poetry and music to be imitative, each varying in imitation by media, object, and manner.[39] For example, music imitates with the media of rhythm and harmony, whereas dance imitates with rhythm alone, and poetry with language. The forms also differ in their object of imitation. Comedy, for instance, is a dramatic imitation of men worse than average; whereas tragedy imitates men slightly better than average. Lastly, the forms differ in their manner of imitation - through narrative or character, through change or no change, and through drama or no drama.[40] Aristotle believed that imitation is natural to mankind and constitutes one of mankind's advantages over animals.[41] While it is believed that Aristotle's Poetics comprised two books - one on comedy and one on tragedy - only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived. Aristotle taught that tragedy is composed of six elements: plot-structure, character, style, spectacle, and lyric poetry.[42] The characters in a tragedy are merely a means of driving the story; and the plot, not the characters, is the chief focus of tragedy. Tragedy is the imitation of action arousing pity and fear, and is meant to effect the catharsis of those same emotions. Aristotle concludes Poetics with a discussion on which, if either, is superior: epic or tragic mimesis. He suggests that because tragedy possesses all the attributes of an epic, possibly possesses additional attributes such as spectacle and music, is more unified, and achieves the aim of its mimesis in shorter scope, it can be considered superior to epic.[43] Aristotle was a keen systematic collector of riddles, folklore, and proverbs; he and his school had a special interest in the riddles of the Delphic Oracle and studied the fables of Aesop.[44] The loss of his works According to a distinction that originates with Aristotle himself, his writings are divisible into two groups: the "exoteric" and the "esoteric".[45] Most scholars have understood this as a distinction between works Aristotle intended for the public (exoteric), and the more technical works (esoteric) intended for the narrower audience of Aristotle's students and other philosophers who were familiar with the jargon and issues typical of the Platonic and Aristotelian schools. Another common assumption is that none of the exoteric works is extant - that all of Aristotle's extant writings are of the esoteric kind. Current knowledge of what exactly the exoteric writings were like is scant and dubious, though many of them may have been in dialogue form. (Fragments of some of Aristotle's dialogues have survived.) Perhaps it is to these that Cicero refers when he characterized Aristotle's writing style as "a river of gold";[46] it is hard for many modern readers to accept that one could seriously so admire the style of those works currently available to us.[47] However, some modern scholars have warned that we cannot know for certain that Cicero's praise was reserved specifically for the exoteric works; a few modern scholars have actually admired the concise writing style found in Aristotle's extant works.[48] One major question in the history of Aristotle's works, then, is how were the exoteric writings all lost, and how did the ones we now possess come to us?[49] The story of the original manuscripts
  • 16. of the esoteric treatises is described by Strabo in his Geography and Plutarch in his Parallel Lives.[50] The manuscripts were left from Aristotle to his successor Theophrastus, who in turn willed them to Neleus of Scepsis. Neleus supposedly took the writings from Athens to Scepsis, where his heirs let them languish in a cellar until the first century BC, when Apellicon of Teos discovered and purchased the manuscripts, bringing them back to Athens. According to the story, Apellicon tried to repair some of the damage that was done during the manuscripts' stay in the basement, introducing a number of errors into the text. When Lucius Cornelius Sulla occupied Athens in 86 BC, he carried off the library of Apellicon to Rome, where they were first published in 60 BC by the grammarian Tyrannion of Amisus and then by philosopher Andronicus of Rhodes. Carnes Lord attributes the popular belief in this story to the fact that it provides "the most plausible explanation for the rapid eclipse of the Peripatetic school after the middle of the third century, and for the absence of widespread knowledge of the specialized treatises of Aristotle throughout the Hellenistic period, as well as for the sudden reappearance of a flourishing Aristotelianism during the first century B.C."[51] Lord voices a number of reservations concerning this story, however. First, the condition of the texts is far too good for them to have suffered considerable damage followed by Apellicon's inexpert attempt at repair. Second, there is "incontrovertible evidence," Lord says, that the treatises were in circulation during the time in which Strabo and Plutarch suggest they were confined within the cellar in Scepsis. Third, the definitive edition of Aristotle's texts seems to have been made in Athens some fifty years before Andronicus supposedly compiled his. And fourth, ancient library catalogues predating Andronicus' intervention list an Aristotelean corpus quite similar to the one we currently possess. Lord sees a number of post-Aristotelean interpolations in the Politics, for example, but is generally confident that the work has come down to us relatively intact. As the influence of the falsafa grew in the West, in part due to Gerard of Cremona's translations and the spread of Averroism, the demand for Aristotle's works grew. William of Moerbeke translated a number of them into Latin. When Thomas Aquinas wrote his theology, working from Moerbeke's translations, the demand for Aristotle's writings grew and the Greek manuscripts returned to the West, stimulating a revival of Aristotelianism in Europe, and ultimately revitalizing European thought through Muslim influence in Spain to fan the embers of the Renaissance. Legacy
  • 17. Early Islamic portrayal of Aristotle Aristotle portrayed in the 1493 Nuremberg Chronicle as a 15th-century-A.D. scholar. Twenty-three hundred years after his death, Aristotle remains one of the most influential people who ever lived. He was the founder of formal logic, pioneered the study of zoology, and left every future scientist and philosopher in his debt through his contributions to the scientific method.[52][53] Despite these accolades, many of Aristotle's errors held back science considerably. Bertrand Russell notes that "almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an attack on some Aristotelian doctrine". Russell also refers to Aristotle's ethics as "repulsive", and calls his logic "as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy". Russell notes that these errors make it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle, until one remembers how large of an advance he made upon all of his predecessors.[54] The immediate influence of Aristotle's work was felt as the Lyceum grew into the Peripatetic school. Aristotle's notable students included Aristoxenus, Dicaearchus, Demetrius of Phalerum, Eudemos of Rhodes, Harpalus, Hephaestion, Meno, Mnason of Phocis, Nicomachus, and Theophrastus. Aristotle's influence over Alexander the Great is seen in the latter's bringing with him on his expedition a host of zoologists, botanists, and researchers. He had also learned a great deal about Persian customs and traditions from his teacher. Although his respect for Aristotle was diminished as his travels made it clear that much of Aristotle's geography was clearly wrong, when the old philosopher released his works to the public, Alexander complained "Thou hast not done well to publish thy acroamatic doctrines; for in what shall I surpass other men if those doctrines wherein I have been trained are to be all men's common property?"[55]
  • 18. Aristotle is referred to as "The Philosopher" by Scholastic thinkers such as Thomas Aquinas. See Summa Theologica, Part I, Question 3, etc. These thinkers blended Aristotelian philosophy with Christianity, bringing the thought of Ancient Greece into the Middle Ages. It required a repudiation of some Aristotelian principles for the sciences and the arts to free themselves for the discovery of modern scientific laws and empirical methods. The medieval English poet Chaucer describes his student as being happy by having At his bedded hed Twenty books clothed in blake or red Of Aristotle and his philosophie The Italian poet Dante says of Aristotle in the first circles of hell, I saw the Master there of those who know, Amid the philosophic family, By all admired, and by all reverenced; There Plato too I saw, and Socrates, Who stood beside him closer than the rest. The German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche has been said to have taken nearly all of his political philosophy from Aristotle.[56] However implausible this is, it is certainly the case that Aristotle's rigid separation of action from production, and his justification of the subservience of slaves and others to the virtue - or arete - of a few justified the ideal of aristocracy. It is Martin Heidegger, not Nietzsche, who elaborated a new interpretation of Aristotle, intended to warrant his deconstruction of scholastic and philosophical tradition. More recently, Alasdair MacIntyre has attempted to reform what he calls the Aristotelian tradition in a way that is anti-elitist and capable of disputing the claims of both liberals and Nietzscheans.[57] List of Aristotle's works Main article: Corpus Aristotelicum Notes and References 1. ^ Jonathan Barnes, "Life and Work" in The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle (1995), p. 9. 2. ^ McLeish, Kenneth (1999). Aristotle: The Great Philosophers. Routledge. p. 5. ISBN 0- 415-92392-1. 3. ^ Bertrand Russell, "A History of Western Philosophy", Simon & Schuster, 1972 4. ^ Peter Green, Alexander of Macedon, 1991 University of California Press, Ltd. Oxford, England. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data, p.58-59 5. ^ Peter Green, Alexander of Macedon, 1991 University of California Press, Ltd. Oxford, England. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data, p.379,459 6. ^ William George Smith,Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology, vol. 3, p. 88
  • 19. 7. ^ Bertrand Russell, "A History of Western Philosophy", Simon & Schuster, 1972 8. ^ Neill, Alex; Aaron Ridley (1995). The Philosophy of Art: Readings Ancient and Modern. McGraw Hill. p. 488. http://www.amazon.com/dp/0070461929/. 9. ^ Jones, W.T. (1980). The Classical Mind: A History of Western Philosophy. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. p. 216. http://www.amazon.com/dp/0155383124/., cf. Vita Marciana 41. 10. ^ Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt by Hildegard Temporini, Wolfgang HaaseAristotle's Will 11. ^ Bocheński, I. M. (1951). Ancient Formal Logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company. 12. ^ a b Bocheński, 1951. 13. ^ Rose, Lynn E. (1968). Aristotle's Syllogistic. Springfield: Charles C Thomas Publisher. 14. ^ Jori, Alberto (2003). Aristotele. Milano: Bruno Mondadori Editore. 15. ^ Aristotle, History of Animals, 2.3. 16. ^ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 17. ^ Aristotle, Meteorology 1.8, trans. E.W. Webster, rev. J. Barnes. 18. ^ Burent, John. 1928. Platonism, Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 61, 103- 104. 19. ^ Aristotle, Physics 2.6 20. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics VIII 1043a 10-30 21. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics IX 1050a 5-10 22. ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics VIII 1045a-b 23. ^ a b Singer, Charles. A short history of biology. Oxford 1931. 24. ^ Emily Kearns, "Animals, knowledge about," in Oxford Classical Dictionary, 3rd ed., 1996, p. 92. 25. ^ Aristotle, of course, is not responsible for the later use made of this idea by clerics. 26. ^ Mason, A History of the Sciences pp 43-44 27. ^ Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought, pp 201-202; see also: Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being 28. ^ Aristotle, De Anima II 3 29. ^ Mason, A History of the Sciences pp 45 30. ^ Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy Vol. 1 pp. 348 31. ^ Harding, Sandra; Merrill B. Hintikka (31 December 1999). Discovering Reality,: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science. Springer. p. 372. http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/9027714967/. 32. ^ Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought, pp 90-91; Mason, A History of the Sciences, p 46 33. ^ Annas, Classical Greek Philosophy pp 252 34. ^ Mason, A History of the Sciences pp 56 35. ^ Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought, pp 90-94; quotation from p 91 36. ^ Annas, Classical Greek Philosophy, p 252 37. ^ Ebenstein, Alan; William Ebenstein (2002). Introduction to Political Thinkers. Wadsworth Group. p. 59. 38. ^ For a different reading of social and economic processes in the Nicomacean Ethics and Politics see Polanyi, K. (1957) "Aristotle Discovers the Economy" in Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi ed. G. Dalton, Boston 1971, 78-115
  • 20. 39. ^ Aristotle, Poetics I 1447a 40. ^ Aristotle, Poetics III 41. ^ Aristotle, Poetics IV 42. ^ Aristotle, Poetics VI 43. ^ Aristotle, Poetics XXVI 44. ^ Temple, Olivia, and Temple, Robert (translators), The Complete Fables By Aesop Penguin Classics, 1998. ISBN 0140446494 Cf. Introduction, pp. xi-xii. 45. ^ Jonathan Barnes, "Life and Work" in The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle (1995), p. 12; Aristotle himself: Nichomachean Ethics 1102a26-27. Aristotle himself never uses the term "esoteric" or "acroamatic". For other passages where Aristotle speaks of exōterikoi logoi, see W. D. Ross, Aristotle's Metaphysics (1953), vol. 2, pp. 408-410. Ross defends an interpretation according to which the phrase, at least in Aristotle's own works, usually refers generally to "discussions not peculiar to the Peripatetic school", rather than to specific works of Aristotle's own. 46. ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius (106BC-43BC). ""flumen orationis aureum fundens Aristoteles"". Academica. http://www2.cddc.vt.edu/gutenberg/1/4/9/7/14970/14970- h/14970-h.htm#BkII_119. Retrieved on 25 January 2007. 47. ^ Barnes, "Life and Work", p. 12. 48. ^ Barnes, "Roman Aristotle", in Gregory Nagy, Greek Literature, Routledge 2001, vol. 8, p. 174 n. 240. 49. ^ The definitive, English study of these questions is Barnes, "Roman Aristotle". 50. ^ "Sulla." 51. ^ Lord, Carnes (1984). Introduction to the Politics, by Aristotle. Chicago: Chicago University Press. p. 11. 52. ^ http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/34560/Aristotle 53. ^ Durant, Will (1926 (2006)). The Story of Philosophy. United States: Simon & Schuster, Inc.. p. 92. ISBN 9780671739164. 54. ^ Bertrand Russell, "A History of Western Philosophy", Simon & Schuster, 1972 55. ^ Plutarch, Life of Alexander 56. ^ Durant, p. 86 57. ^ Kelvin Knight, Aristotelian Philosophy, Polity Press, 2007, passim. Further reading The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. The following references are only a small selection. · Ackrill J. L . 2001. Essays on Plato and Aristotle, Oxford University Press, USA · Adler, Mortimer J . (1978). Aristotle for Everybody. New York: Macmillan. A popular exposition for the general reader. · Bakalis Nikolaos. 2005. Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments, Trafford Publishing ISBN 1-4120-4843-5 · Barnes J. 1995. The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, Cambridge University Press · Bocheński, I. M . (1951). Ancient Formal Logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.
  • 21. · Bolotin, David (1998). An Approach to Aristotle's Physics: With Particular Attention to the Role of His Manner of Writing. Albany: SUNY Press. A contribution to our understanding of how to read Aristotle's scientific works. · Burnyeat, M. F . et al. 1979. Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics. Oxford: Sub-faculty of Philosophy · Chappell, V. 1973. Aristotle's Conception of Matter, Journal of Philosophy 70: 679-696 · Code, Alan. 1995. Potentiality in Aristotle's Science and Metaphysics, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76 · Frede, Michael. 1987. Essays in Ancient Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press · Gill, Mary Louise. 1989. Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity. Princeton: Princeton University Press · Guthrie, W. K. C. (1981). A History of Greek Philosophy, Vol. 6. Cambridge University Press. · Halper, Edward C. (2007) One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 1: Books Alpha — Delta, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-21-6 · Halper, Edward C. (2005) One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 2: The Central Books, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-05-6 · Irwin, T. H. 1988. Aristotle's First Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press · Jori, Alberto . 2003. Aristotele, Milano: Bruno Mondadori Editore (Prize 2003 of the "International Academy of the History of Science") ISBN 88-424-9737-1 · Knight, Kelvin. 2007. Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre, Polity Press. · Lewis, Frank A. 1991. Substance and Predication in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. · Lloyd, G. E. R . 1968. Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of his Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Pr., ISBN 0-521-09456-9. · Lord, Carnes. 1984. Introduction to The Politics, by Aristotle. Chicago: Chicago University Press. · Loux, Michael J. 1991. Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle's Metaphysics Ζ and Η. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press · Owen, G. E. L. 1965c. The Platonism of Aristotle, Proceedings of the British Academy 50 125-150. Reprinted in J. Barnes, M. Schofield, and R. R. K. Sorabji (eds.), Articles on Aristotle, Vol 1. Science. London: Duckworth (1975). 14-34 · Pangle, Lorraine Smith (2003). Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Aristotle's conception of the deepest human relationship viewed in the light of the history of philosophic thought on friendship. · Reeve, C. D. C. 2000. Substantial Knowledge: Aristotle's Metaphysics. Indianapolis: Hackett. · Rose, Lynn E . (1968). Aristotle's Syllogistic. Springfield: Charles C Thomas Publisher. · Ross, Sir David (1995). Aristotle (6th ed. ed.). London: Routledge. An classic overview by one of Aristotle's most prominent English translators, in print since 1923. · Scaltsas, T. 1994. Substances and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. · Strauss, Leo. "On Aristotle's Politics" (1964), in The City and Man, Chicago; Rand McNally.
  • 22. · Taylor, Henry Osborn (1922). "Chapter 3: Aristotle's Biology". Greek Biology and Medicine. http://web.archive.org/web/20060327222953/http://www.ancientlibrary.com/medicine/00 51.html. · Veatch, Henry B . (1974). Aristotle: A Contemporary Appreciation. Bloomington: Indiana U. Press. For the general reader. · Woods, M. J. 1991b. "Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle's Metaphysics." Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy supplement. 41-56 Terjemah Aristotle (Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης Aristotélēs) (384 SM - 322 SM) adalah seorang filsuf Yunani, seorang pelajar dari Plato dan guru dari Alexander the Great. He wrote on many subjects, including physics, metaphysics , poetry , theater, music, logic, rhetoric, politics, government, ethics, biology and zoology. Dia menulis di banyak mata pelajaran, termasuk fisika, metafisika, puisi, teater, musik, logika, retorika, politik, pemerintahan, etika, biologi dan zoology. Together with Plato and Socrates (Plato's teacher), Aristotle is one of the most important founding figures in Western philosophy . Bersama dengan Plato dan Socrates (guru Plato), Aristotle adalah salah satu yang paling penting dalam mendirikan tokoh filsafat Barat. He was the first to create a comprehensive system of Western philosophy, encompassing morality and aesthetics, logic and science, politics and metaphysics. Dia adalah yang pertama untuk membuat suatu sistem filsafat Barat, meliputi moralitas dan estetika, logika dan ilmu pengetahuan, politik dan metafisika. Aristotle's views on the physical sciences profoundly shaped medieval scholarship, and their influence extended well into the Renaissance , although they were ultimately replaced by modern physics . Aristotle's dilihat pada fisik ilmu profoundly abad berbentuk beasiswa, dan pengaruh mereka diperpanjang baik ke Renaisans, meskipun mereka akhirnya digantikan oleh fisika modern. In the biological sciences, some of his observations were only confirmed to be accurate in the nineteenth century. Dalam ilmu biologi, beberapa orang hanya pengamatan dikonfirmasi menjadi akurat dalam abad kesembilanbelas. His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, which were incorporated in the late nineteenth century into modern formal logic . Karya-karyanya mengandung paling awal formal dikenal ilmu logika, yang tergabung pada akhir abad ke sembilan belas modern formal logika. In metaphysics, Aristotelianism had a profound influence on philosophical and theological thinking in the Islamic and Jewish traditions in the Middle Ages , and it continues to influence Christian theology , especially Eastern Orthodox theology , and the scholastic tradition of the Roman Catholic Church . Dalam metafisika, Aristotelianism memiliki pengaruh besar pada pemikiran filosofis dan teologi dalam tradisi Islam dan Yahudi di abad pertengahan, dan terus mempengaruhi teologi Kristen, khususnya teologi Ortodoks Timur, dan sekolah dari tradisi Gereja Katolik Roma. All aspects of Aristotle's philosophy continue to be the object of active academic study today. Semua aspek filosofi Aristotel terus menjadi objek studi akademis aktif hari ini.
  • 23. Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues ( Cicero described his literary style as "a river of gold"), it is thought that the majority of his writings are now lost and only about one third of the original works have survived. [ 1 ] Walaupun Aristotle menulis banyak treatises elegan dan dialog (Cicero dijelaskan kepada sastra gaya sebagai "sungai emas"), ia berpikir bahwa sebagian besar tulisannya telah hilang dan hanya sekitar sepertiga dari karya asli yang bertahan hidup. [1] Contents Isi [hide] · 1 Life 1 Hidup · 2 Logic 2 Logic o 2.1 History Sejarah 2,1 o 2.2 Analytics and the Organon 2,2 Analytics dan Organon · 3 Aristotle's scientific method 3 Aristotle's metode ilmiah · 4 Physics 4 Fisika o 4.1 The five elements 4.1 lima elemen o 4.2 Causality, The Four Causes 4,2 hubungan sebab dan akibat, Empat Penyebab o 4.3 Chance and spontaneity Kemungkinan 4,3 dan spontanitas · 5 Metaphysics 5 metafisika o 5.1 Substance, potentiality and actuality 5,1 Substansi, potensi dan actuality o 5.2 Universals and particulars 5,2 Universals dan fakta-fakta · 6 Biology and medicine 6 Biologi dan Obat o 6.1 Empirical research program 6,1 empiris program penelitian o 6.2 Classification of living things 6,2 Klasifikasi hidup hal o 6.3 Theory of biological forms and souls 6,3 Theory of biologi bentuk dan jiwa o 6.4 Aristotle's successor: Theophrastus 6,4 Aristotle's penerus: Theophrastus o 6.5 Influence on Hellenistic medicine Pengaruh 6,5 pada Helenistik obat · 7 Practical Philosophy 7 Praktis Filosofi o 7.1 Ethics 7,1 Kode Etik o 7.2 Politics 7,2 Politik o 7.3 Rhetoric and poetics 7,3 retorika dan poetics · 8 The loss of his works 8 Hilangnya karya-karyanya · 9 Legacy 9 Legacy · 10 List of Aristotle's works 10 Daftar Aristotle's works · 11 Notes and References 11 Catatan dan Referensi · 12 Further reading 12 Lebih lanjut membaca · 13 See also 13 Lihat juga · 14 External links 14 Pranala luar o 14.1 Collections of Aristotle's works Koleksi dari 14,1 Aristotle's works o 14.2 Articles on Aristotle Artikel pada 14,2 Aristotel Life Kehidupan
  • 24. Aristotle was born in Stageira , Chalcidice , in 384 BC, about 55 km east of modern-day Thessaloniki . [ 2 ] His father, Nicomachus was the personal physician to King Amyntas of Macedon . Aristotle lahir di Stageira, Chalcidice, pada 384 SM, sekitar 55 kilometer sebelah timur modern hari Thessaloniki. [2] Ayahnya, Nicomachus adalah dokter pribadi ke Raja Amyntas dari Macedon. Aristotle was trained and educated as a member of the aristocracy . Aristotel telah dididik dan dilatih sebagai anggota dari aristokrasi. At about the age of eighteen, he went to Athens to continue his education at Plato's Academy . Pada usia sekitar delapan belas, dia pergi ke Jakarta untuk melanjutkan pendidikan di Akademi Plato's. Aristotle remained at the academy for nearly twenty years, not leaving until after Plato's death in 347 BC. Aristotel tetap di akademi selama hampir dua puluh tahun, tidak meninggalkan Plato sampai setelah kematian di 347 SM. He then traveled with Xenocrates to the court of his friend Hermias of Atarneus in Asia Minor. Kemudian dia bepergian dengan Xenocrates ke pengadilan kepada teman Hermias dari Atarneus di Asia Minor. While in Asia, Aristotle traveled with Theophrastus to the island of Lesbos , where together they researched the botany and zoology of the island. Sementara di Asia, Aristotle bepergian dengan Theophrastus ke pulau Lesbos, di mana mereka bersama-sama dengan penelitian botani dan zoology dari pulau itu. Aristotle married Hermias's adoptive daughter (or niece) Pythias . Aristotel menikah Hermias's adoptive putri (atau keponakan) Pythias. She bore him a daughter, whom they named Pythias. Dia membosankan seorang anak perempuan, yang bernama Pythias mereka. Soon after Hermias' death, Aristotle was invited by Philip of Macedon to become tutor to Alexander the Great in 343 BC [ 3 ] Segera setelah Hermias' kematian, Aristotle diundang oleh Philip dari Macedon menjadi tutor untuk Alexander the Great pada 343 SM [3] During his time as the head of Macedon's royal academy, Aristotle gave lessons not only to Alexander, but also to two other future kings: Ptolemy and Cassander . Selama waktu sebagai kepala Macedon dari akademi kerajaan, Aristotle memberi pelajaran tidak hanya untuk Alexander, tetapi juga untuk masa depan dua raja: Ptolemy dan Cassander. In his Politics , Aristotle states that only one thing could justify monarchy, and that was if the virtue of the king and his family were greater than the virtue of the rest of the citizens put together. Dalam Politik, Aristotle menyatakan bahwa hanya satu hal yang dapat membenarkan monarki, dan yang jika kebaikan raja dan keluarganya yang lebih besar daripada kebaikan sisanya warga kota mengumpulkan. Tactfully, he included the young prince and his father in that category. Dgn bijaksana, dia termasuk anak raja dan ayahnya dalam kategori tersebut. Aristotle encouraged Alexander toward eastern conquest, and his attitude towards Persia was unabashedly ethnocentric. Aristotel didorong ke arah timur penaklukan Alexander, dan sikap terhadap Persia telah unabashedly ethnocentric. In one famous example, he counsels Alexander to be 'a leader to the Greeks and a despot to the barbarians, to look after the former as after friends and relatives, and to deal with the latter as with beasts or plants'. [ 4 ] Near the end of Alexander's life he began to suspect plots, and threatened Aristotle in letters. Dalam satu contoh terkenal, Alexander counsels ia akan menjadi 'pemimpin ke Yunani dan orang lalim kepada barbarians, untuk memelihara setelah mantan sebagai teman dan keluarga, dan untuk menangani dengan kedua sebagai dengan binatang atau tanaman. [4] dekat akhir Alexander kehidupan dia mulai mencurigai plots, dan terancam di Aristotel huruf. Aristotle had made no secret of his contempt for Alexander's pretense of divinity, and the king had executed Aristotle's grand-nephew Callisthenes as a traitor. Aristotel telah dibuat tidak rahasia orang hina untuk Alexander dari tuntutan dari keilahian, dan raja telah dijalankan Aristotle's grand-keponakan Callisthenes
  • 25. sebagai pengkhianat. A widespread tradition in antiquity suspected Aristotle of playing a role in Alexander's death, but there is little evidence for this. [ 5 ] J luas dalam tradisi jaman dahulu dari diputar Aristotel diduga berperan dalam Alexander kematian, tetapi ada sedikit bukti untuk ini. [5] By 335 BC he had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the Lyceum . 335 SM oleh dia kembali ke Jakarta, mendirikan sekolah itu sendiri dikenal sebagai kamar bacaan. Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years. Aristotel kursus dilakukan di sekolah selama dua belas tahun. While in Athens, his wife Pythias died, and Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stageira , who bore him a son whom he named after his father, Nicomachus . Sedangkan di Jakarta, istrinya Pythias meninggal, Aristotle dan menjadi terlibat dengan Herpyllis dari Stageira, yang membosankan dia seorang anak laki-laki yang dinamakannya setelah ayahnya, Nicomachus. According to the Suda , he also had an eromenos , Palaephatus of Abydus . [ 6 ] Menurut Suda, dia juga memiliki eromenos, Palaephatus dari Abydus. [6] It is during this period in Athens from 335 BC to 323 BC when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his works. [ 7 ] Aristotle wrote many dialogues, only fragments of which survived. Adalah selama periode ini di Athena dari 335 SM ke 323 SM ketika Aristotel diyakini memiliki banyak terdiri dari karya-karyanya. [7] Aristotle menulis banyak dialog, hanya fragmen yang selamat. The works that have survived are in treatise form and were not, for the most part, intended for widespread publication, as they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students. Pekerjaan yang telah bertahan dalam risalah formulir dan tidak, sebagian besar, yang dimaksudkan untuk publikasi luas, karena biasanya pemikiran untuk kuliah bantu untuk siswa. His most important treatises include Physics , Metaphysics , Nicomachean Ethics , Politics , De Anima (On the Soul) and Poetics . His paling penting termasuk treatises Fisika, metaphysics, Nicomachean Etika, Politik, De anima (On the Soul) dan Poetics. Aristotle not only studied almost every subject possible at the time, but made significant contributions to most of them. Aristotle tidak hanya belajar mata pelajaran yang mungkin hampir setiap saat, tetapi kontribusi yang signifikan kebanyakan mereka. In physical science, Aristotle studied anatomy, astronomy, economics, embryology , geography, geology, meteorology, physics and zoology. Dalam ilmu fisik, Aristotle mempelajari anatomi, astronomi, ekonomi, embriologi, geografi, geologi, meteorologi, fisika dan zoology. In philosophy, he wrote on aesthetics, ethics, government, metaphysics, politics, psychology, rhetoric and theology. Dalam filsafat, dia wrote estetika, etika, pemerintah, metafisika, politik, psikologi, retorika dan teologi. He also studied education, foreign customs, literature and poetry. Dia juga belajar pendidikan, adat asing, sastra dan puisi. His combined works constitute a virtual encyclopedia of Greek knowledge. Ia bekerja merupakan gabungan virtual ensiklopedia pengetahuan dari Yunani. It has been suggested that Aristotle was probably the last person to know everything there was to be known in his own time. [ 8 ] Telah menyarankan bahwa Aristotle mungkin terakhir orang mengetahui segala sesuatu ada dikenal dalam waktu sendiri. [8] Upon Alexander's death, anti-Macedonian sentiment in Athens once again flared. Eurymedon the hierophant denounced Aristotle for not holding the gods in honor. Setelah kematian Alexander, sentimen anti-Macedonia di Jakarta sekali lagi flared. Eurymedon yang hierophant denounced Aristotle untuk tidak memegang allah dalam kehormatan. Aristotle fled the city to his mother's
  • 26. family estate in Chalcis , explaining, "I will not allow the Athenians to sin twice against philosophy ," [ 9 ] a reference to Athens's prior trial and execution of Socrates. Aristotel melarikan diri ke kota ibunya keluarga estate di Chalcis, menjelaskan, "Saya tidak akan mengizinkan Athenians berdosa dua kali terhadap filsafat," [9] referensi sebelumnya dari Jakarta ke pengadilan dan pelaksanaan Socrates. However, he died in Euboea of natural causes within the year (in 322 BC). Namun, ia meninggal di Euboea penyebab dari alam dalam tahun (pada 322 sebelum masehi). Aristotle named chief executor his student Antipater and left a will in which he asked to be buried next to his wife. [ 10 ] Aristotel bernama ketua pelaksana his siswa Antipater dan kiri yang akan di mana ia harus dikubur di samping istrinya. [10] Logic Logika Main article: Term logic Artikel utama: Istilah logika For more details on this topic, see Non-Aristotelian logic . Untuk informasi lebih rinci tentang topik ini, lihat Non-Aristotel logika. Aristotle's conception of logic was the dominant form of logic until 19th century advances in mathematical logic . Kant stated in the Critique of Pure Reason that Aristotle's theory of logic completely accounted for the core of deductive inference. Aristotle's konsep dari logika dominan adalah bentuk logika sampai abad ke-19 kemajuan dalam logika matematika. Kant dalam Critique of Pure Reason yang Aristotle's teori logika sepenuhnya merupakan inti dari kesimpulan deduktif. History Sejarah Aristotle "says that 'on the subject of reasoning' he 'had nothing else on an earlier date to speak of'". [ 11 ] However, Plato reports that syntax was devised before him, by Prodicus of Ceos , who was concerned by the correct use of words. Aristotle "mengatakan bahwa 'pada subyek reasoning' dia 'sudah tidak ada lagi pada tanggal yang lebih awal untuk berbicara tentang'". [11] Namun, Plato laporan bahwa sintaks telah dibuat sebelum dia, oleh Prodicus dari Ceos, yang bersangkutan dengan benar menggunakan kata-kata. Logic seems to have emerged from dialectics ; the earlier philosophers made frequent use of concepts like reductio ad absurdum in their discussions, but never truly understood the logical implications. Logika tampaknya telah muncul dari dialektika, yang sebelumnya dilakukan filosof sering menggunakan konsep seperti reductio iklan absurdum dalam diskusi mereka, tetapi tidak pernah benar-benar memahami implikasi logis. Even Plato had difficulties with logic; although he had a reasonable conception of a deduction system, he could never actually construct one and relied instead on his dialectic . [ 12 ] Plato believed that deduction would simply follow from premises , hence he focused on maintaining solid premises so that the conclusion would logically follow. Plato bahkan pernah kesulitan dengan logika, walaupun ia memiliki konsep yang wajar deduction sistem, ia tidak pernah benar-benar dapat membangun dan diandalkan, bukan pada dialectic. [12] Plato percaya bahwa deduction akan cukup ikuti dari lokasi, maka ia fokus pada pemeliharaan solid lokasi sehingga kesimpulan logis akan mengikuti. Consequently, Plato realized that a method for obtaining conclusions would be most beneficial. Akibatnya, Plato menyadari bahwa metode untuk memperoleh kesimpulan akan paling bermanfaat. He never succeeded in devising such a method, but his best attempt was published in his book Sophist , where he introduced his division
  • 27. method. [ 13 ] Ia tidak pernah berhasil dalam suatu metode devising, tapi ia mencoba terbaik dimuat dalam bukunya pandangannya, di mana dia diperkenalkan kepada divisi metode. [13] Analytics and the Organon Analisis dan Organon Main article: Organon Artikel utama: Organon What we today call Aristotelian logic , Aristotle himself would have labeled "analytics". Apa yang kita panggil hari ini Aristotel logika, Aristotle dirinya akan berlabel "analisis". The term "logic" he reserved to mean dialectics . Istilah "logika" berarti ia reserved dialektika. Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, since it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. Sebagian besar dari pekerjaan Aristotle mungkin tidak dalam bentuk aslinya, karena kemungkinan besar diedit oleh mahasiswa dan dosen nantinya. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into six books in about the early 1st century AD: Yang logis dari Aristotle telah dikompilasi ke dalam enam buku sekitar awal abad 1. AD: 1. Categories Kategori 2. On Interpretation Pada Interpretation 3. Prior Analytics Sebelum Analytics 4. Posterior Analytics Posterior Analytics 5. Topics Topik 6. On Sophistical Refutations Pada Sophistical Refutations The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. Pesanan buku-buku (atau ajaran dari mereka yang terdiri) tidak pasti, namun daftar ini adalah berasal dari analisis dari tulisan-tulisan Aristotle. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the Categories, to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms (in the Analytics) and dialectics (in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations). It goes dari dasar, analisis sederhana istilah dalam Kategori, untuk studi yang lebih kompleks bentuk, yaitu, syllogisms (dalam Analytics) dan dialektika (dalam Topik dan Sophistical Refutations). There is one volume of Aristotle's concerning logic not found in the Organon , namely the fourth book of Metaphysics. . [ 12 ] Ada satu volume Aristotle's tentang logika tidak ditemukan di Organon, yaitu empat buku metafisika.. [12] Aristotle's scientific method Aristotle's metode ilmiah
  • 28. Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of The School of Athens , a fresco by Raphael . Plato (kiri) dan Aristotle (kanan), sebuah detail di School of Athens, sebuah lukisan dinding oleh Raphael. Aristotle gestures to the earth, representing his belief in knowledge through empirical observation and experience, while holding a copy of his Nicomachean Ethics in his hand, whilst Plato gestures to the heavens, representing his belief in The Forms . Aristotel gerak-gerik ke bumi, yang merupakan kepercayaan kepada pengetahuan melalui pengamatan dan pengalaman empiris, sementara memegang salinan nya Nicomachean Etika di tangannya, sementara gerak-gerik Plato ke langit, ia mewakili kepercayaan di Formulir. For more details on this topic, see Aristotle's theory of universals . Untuk informasi lebih rinci tentang topik ini, lihat dari teori Aristotle universals. Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the universal . Seperti itu guru Plato, Aristotle filosofi bertujuan yang universal. Aristotle, however, found the universal in particular things, which he called the essence of things, while Plato finds that the universal exists apart from particular things, and is related to them as their prototype or exemplar . Aristotel Namun, menemukan universal khususnya hal-hal yang ia disebut inti dari sesuatu, sedangkan Plato menemukan bahwa ada yang universal selain dari hal-hal tertentu, dan berhubungan dengan mereka sebagai prototipe atau contoh. For Aristotle, therefore, philosophic method implies the ascent from the study of particular phenomena to the knowledge of essences, while for Plato philosophic method means the descent from a knowledge of universal Forms (or ideas) to a contemplation of particular imitations of these. Aristotel Untuk itu, metode filosofis yang menunjukkan kenaikan dari studi khusus untuk fenomena pengetahuan essences, sedangkan untuk metode filosofis Plato berarti keturunan dari pengetahuan tentang universal Formulir (atau gagasan) ke kontemplasi tertentu imitations ini. For Aristotle, "form" still refers to the unconditional basis of phenomena but is "instantiated" in a particular substance (see Universals and particulars , below). Untuk Aristotel, "bentuk" masih merujuk pada tak bersyarat dasar fenomena tetapi "instantiated" dalam substansi tertentu (lihat Universals dan fakta-fakta, di bawah). In a certain sense, Aristotle's method is both inductive and deductive , while Plato's is essentially deductive from a priori principles. [ 14 ] Dalam beberapa hal, Aristotle dari kedua metode induktif dan deduktif, sementara pada dasarnya adalah Plato's deduktif dari priori prinsip. [14] In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, biology and other natural sciences. Dalam terminologi Aristotle's, "filosofi alam" adalah cabang filosofi yang meneliti fenomena alam di dunia, dan mencakup bidang yang akan hari ini dianggap sebagai fisika, biologi dan ilmu alam lainnya. In modern times, the scope of philosophy has become limited to more generic or abstract inquiries, such as ethics and metaphysics, in which logic plays a major role. Dalam modern, lingkup filsafat telah menjadi terbatas untuk lebih umum atau abstrak inquiries, seperti etika dan metafisika, dimana logika memainkan peran utama. Today's philosophy tends to exclude empirical study of the natural world by means of the scientific method . Today filosofi cenderung mengecualikan empiris ilmu alam dunia dengan cara yang metode ilmiah. In contrast, Aristotle's philosophical endeavors encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. Sebaliknya, Aristotle's filosofis berusaha mencakup hampir semua aspek dari penyelidikan intelektual.
  • 29. In the larger sense of the word, Aristotle makes philosophy coextensive with reasoning, which he also would describe as "science". Lebih besar dalam arti kata, menjadikan filosofi Aristotel coextensive dengan alasan, dia juga yang akan menjelaskan sebagai "ilmu". Note, however, that his use of the term science carries a different meaning than that covered by the term " scientific method ". Namun, perlu diketahui bahwa penggunaan istilah ilmu membawa makna yang berbeda dari yang tercakup dalam istilah "metode ilmiah". For Aristotle, "all science ( dianoia ) is either practical, poetical or theoretical" ( Metaphysics 1025b25). Untuk Aristotel, "semua ilmu (dianoia) adalah salah satu praktis, puitis atau teoritis" (metaphysics 1025b25). By practical science, he means ethics and politics; by poetical science, he means the study of poetry and the other fine arts; by theoretical science, he means physics, mathematics and metaphysics. Praktis oleh ilmu pengetahuan, berarti ia etika dan politik; puitis oleh ilmu pengetahuan, berarti ia belajar puisi dan seni rupa yang lain; oleh teori ilmu pengetahuan, berarti ia fisika, matematika dan metafisika. If logic (or "analytics") is regarded as a study preliminary to philosophy, the divisions of Aristotelian philosophy would consist of: (1) Logic ; (2) Theoretical Philosophy, including Metaphysics, Physics, Mathematics, (3) Practical Philosophy and (4) Poetical Philosophy. Jika logika (atau "analisis") yang dianggap sebagai sebuah awal untuk belajar filsafat, maka divisi dari filosofi Aristotel akan terdiri dari: (1) Logika; (2) Theoretical Philosophy, termasuk metafisika, Fisika, Matematika, (3) praktis dan Filosofi (4) Filosofi puitis. In the period between his two stays in Athens, between his times at the Academy and the Lyceum, Aristotle conducted most of the scientific thinking and research for which he is renowned today. Pada periode antara dua tetap di Jakarta, antara nya kali di Akademi dan kamar bacaan, Aristotle dilakukan sebagian besar berpikir dan penelitian ilmiah yang ia terkenal hari ini. In fact, most of Aristotle's life was devoted to the study of the objects of natural science. Bahkan, sebagian besar dari Aristotle Hidup dikhususkan untuk ilmu obyek dari ilmu alam. Aristotle's metaphysics contains observations on the nature of numbers but he made no original contributions to mathematics. Aristotle's metaphysics berisi observasi pada sifat nomor tetapi ia tidak asli kontribusi kepada matematika. He did, however, perform original research in the natural sciences, eg, botany, zoology, physics, astronomy, chemistry, meteorology, and several other sciences. Dia, bagaimanapun, melakukan penelitian asli dalam ilmu alam, misalnya, botani, zoology, fisika, astronomi, kimia, meteorologi, dan beberapa ilmu lainnya. Aristotle's writings on science are largely qualitative, as opposed to quantitative. Aristotel dari tulisan-tulisan tentang ilmu pengetahuan yang sangat kualitatif, karena bertentangan dengan kuantitatif. Beginning in the sixteenth century, scientists began applying mathematics to the physical sciences, and Aristotle's work in this area was deemed hopelessly inadequate. Pada awal abad keenambelas, ilmuwan matematika untuk mulai menerapkan ilmu yang fisik, dan Aristotle's bekerja di daerah ini hopelessly dianggap kurang memadai. His failings were largely due to the absence of concepts like mass, velocity, force and temperature. His failings yang sebagian besar disebabkan oleh tidak adanya konsep seperti massa, kecepatan, kekuatan dan suhu. He had a conception of speed and temperature, but no quantitative understanding of them, which was partly due to the absence of basic experimental devices, like clocks and thermometers. Dia memiliki konsep dari kecepatan dan suhu, tapi tidak ada kuantitatif pemahaman mereka, yang sebagian karena tidak adanya dasar eksperimental perangkat, seperti jam dan termometer.
  • 30. A green and red Perseid meteor is striking the sky just below the Milky Way in August 2007. J hijau dan merah Perseid meteor mengesankan adalah tepat di bawah langit yang Bimasakti pada bulan Agustus 2007. His writings provide an account of many scientific observations, a mixture of precocious accuracy and curious errors. Tulisannya memberikan banyak rekening ilmiah observasi, campuran sebelum waktunya curious akurasi dan kesalahan. For example, in his History of Animals he claimed that human males have more teeth than females. [ 15 ] In a similar vein, John Philoponus , and later Galileo , showed by simple experiments that Aristotle's theory that a heavier object falls faster than a lighter object is incorrect. [ 16 ] On the other hand, Aristotle refuted Democritus 's claim that the Milky Way was made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out (correctly, even if such reasoning was bound to be dismissed for a long time) that, given "current astronomical demonstrations" that "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then...the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them." [ 17 ] Misalnya, dalam Sejarah Binatang ia menyatakan bahwa manusia laki-laki memiliki lebih dari gigi perempuan. [15] Dalam nada yang sama, John Philoponus, dan kemudian Galileo, menunjukkan bahwa percobaan sederhana oleh Aristotle's teori bahwa benda berat jatuh lebih cepat dari yang ringan objek tidak benar. [16] Di sisi lain, Aristotle refuted Democritus' s klaim bahwa Bimasakti dibuat dari "orang-bintang yang berbayang dari oleh bumi dari sinar matahari," pointing out (dengan benar, bahkan jika reasoning telah terikat akan diberhentikan untuk waktu yang lama) itu, diberikan "sekarang astronomi demonstrasi" yang "ukuran matahari lebih besar daripada yang di bumi dan jarak dari bintang-bintang dari bumi berkali-kali lebih besar dari yang matahari, maka ... matahari bersinar di seluruh bumi dan bintang layar none of them. "[17] In places, Aristotle goes too far in deriving 'laws of the universe' from simple observation and over-stretched reason . Di tempat, Aristotle pergi terlalu jauh dalam deriving 'hukum alam semesta' dari pengamatan sederhana dan over-stretched alasan. Today's scientific method assumes that such thinking without sufficient facts is ineffective, and that discerning the validity of one's hypothesis requires far more rigorous experimentation than that which Aristotle used to support his laws. Hari metode ilmiah dengan menganggap bahwa tanpa memikirkan fakta-fakta yang cukup efektif, dan yang cerdas validitas satu dari hipotesa memerlukan eksperimentasi jauh lebih ketat daripada yang Aristotel digunakan untuk mendukung undang-undang. Aristotle also had some scientific blind spots. Aristotle juga mempunyai beberapa ilmiah buta tempat itu. He posited a geocentric cosmology that we may discern in selections of the Metaphysics , which was widely accepted up until the 1500s. Dia posited yang geocentric
  • 31. kosmologi bahwa kami dapat memahami dalam pilihan dari metafisika, yang diterima secara luas sampai 1500s. From the 3rd century to the 1500s, the dominant view held that the Earth was the center of the universe ( geocentrism ). 3. Dari abad ke 1500s, yang dominan diselenggarakan melihat bahwa Bumi adalah pusat alam semesta (geocentrism). Since he was perhaps the philosopher most respected by European thinkers during and after the Renaissance, these thinkers often took Aristotle's erroneous positions as given, which held back science in this epoch. [ 18 ] However, Aristotle's scientific shortcomings should not mislead one into forgetting his great advances in the many scientific fields. Sejak dia mungkin filsuf yang paling dihormati oleh pemikir Eropa selama dan setelah Renaissance, pemikir ini sering mengambil Aristotle's salah posisi seperti yang diberikan, yang diselenggarakan kembali sains di masa ini. [18] Namun, Aristotle's ilmiah kekurangan seharusnya tidak menyesatkan satu menjadi melupakan dia kemajuan besar dalam berbagai bidang ilmu. For instance, he founded logic as a formal science and created foundations to biology that were not superseded for two millennia. Sebagai contoh, ia didirikan sebagai logika formal sains dan membuat yayasan untuk biologi yang tidak superseded selama dua ribuan tahun. Moreover, he introduced the fundamental notion that nature is composed of things that change and that studying such changes can provide useful knowledge of underlying constants. Selain itu, dia memperkenalkan mendasar bahwa alam terdiri dari hal-hal yang berubah dan perubahan yang belajar seperti itu dapat memberikan pengetahuan yang berguna konstan. Physics Fisika Main article: Physics (Aristotle) Artikel utama: Fisika (Aristotle) The five elements Lima elemen Main article: Classical element Artikel utama: Klasik elemen · Fire , which is hot and dry. Api, yang panas dan kering. · Earth , which is cold and dry. Bumi, yang dingin dan kering. · Air , which is hot and wet. Udara yang panas dan basah. · Water , which is cold and wet. Air yang dingin dan basah. · Aether , which is the divine substance that makes up the heavenly spheres and heavenly bodies (stars and planets). Aether, yang merupakan substansi ilahi yang membuat sampai di langit spheres dan badan-badan langit (bintang dan planets). Each of the four earthly elements has its natural place; the earth at the centre of the universe, then water, then air, then fire. Masing-masing dari empat elemen dunia memiliki tempat alam; bumi di pusat alam semesta, maka air, maka udara, maka api. When they are out of their natural place they have natural motion, requiring no external cause, which is towards that place; so bodies sink in water, air bubbles up, rain falls, flame rises in air. Apabila mereka dari tempat mereka alami alam gerakan mereka, tidak memerlukan penyebab eksternal, yang menuju tempat itu, maka tubuh masuk ke dalam air, sampai gelembung udara, hujan, api di udara meningkat. The heavenly element has perpetual circular motion. Di langit yang terus-elemen gerakan melingkar.
  • 32. Causality, The Four Causes Hubungan sebab dan akibat, Empat Penyebab Main article: Four causes Artikel utama: Empat menyebabkan · The material cause is that from which a thing comes into existence as from its part, constituents, substratum or materials. Materi yang menyebabkan adalah sebuah hal yang datang ke dalam keberadaan sebagai bagian dari, konstituen, atau bahan-bahan dasar. This reduces the explanation of causes to the parts (factors, elements, constituents, ingredients) forming the whole (system, structure, compound, complex, composite, or combination), a relationship known as the part-whole causation. Ini akan mengurangi penjelasan tentang penyebab ke bagian (faktor, elemen, konstituen, bahan) membentuk keseluruhan (sistem, struktur, kompleks, rumit, komposit, atau kombinasi), sebuah hubungan yang dikenal sebagai bagian-hal menyebabkan seluruh. Simply put it is the influence of the material substances on the event. Simply put it is pengaruh materi bahan pada acara tersebut. So imagine two dominos, the first of which is lighter. Jadi bayangkan dua dominos, pertama yang lebih ringan. The first is knocked over into the second but does not have enough power to knock it over, this is Material cause. Yang pertama adalah knocked over menjadi yang kedua tetapi tidak memiliki cukup kuasa untuk merobohkan lebih dari itu, hal ini menyebabkan Bahan. · The formal cause tells us what a thing is, that any thing is determined by the definition, form, pattern, essence, whole, synthesis or archetype. Formal menyebabkan memberitahu kami apa yang hal itu, bahwa hal itu ditentukan oleh definisi, bentuk, pola, inti, seluruh, sintesis atau pola dasar. It embraces the account of causes in terms of fundamental principles or general laws, as the whole (ie, macrostructure) is the cause of its parts, a relationship known as the whole-part causation. It meliputi rekening penyebab dari segi prinsip-prinsip umum atau undang-undang, sebagai keseluruhan (yakni, macrostructure) adalah penyebab komponen, yang dikenal sebagai hubungan seluruh bagian-hal menyebabkan. Plainly put it is the influence of the form (essence) of the things on the event. Terangnya menaruhnya adalah pengaruh dalam bentuk (inti) dari hal-hal di acara itu. So take the two dominos again except this time the second is shaped to prevent it from falling *eg. Jadi mengambil dua dominos lagi kecuali kali ini adalah yang kedua berbentuk untuk mencegah dari jatuh * misalnya. triangular.* this is formal cause. segitiga .* ini menyebabkan formal. · The efficient cause is that from which the change or the ending of the change first starts. Yang efisien adalah bahwa dari mana perubahan atau akhir dari perubahan pertama dimulai. It identifies 'what makes of what is made and what causes change of what is changed' and so suggests all sorts of agents, nonliving or living, acting as the sources of change or movement or rest. It mengenalpasti 'apa yang membuat apa yang dilakukan dan apa yang menyebabkan perubahan apa yang berubah' dan menyarankan agar semua jenis agen, yg tdk hidup atau hidup, yang bertindak sebagai sumber perubahan atau gerakan atau beristirahat. Representing the current understanding of causality as the relation of cause and effect, this covers the modern definitions of "cause" as either the agent or agency or particular events or states of affairs. Mewakili saat ini pemahaman tentang hubungan sebab dan akibat sebagai hubungan yang menyebabkan dan efek, yang modern ini mencakup definisi "menyebabkan" sebagai salah satu agen atau agen atau peristiwa tertentu atau urusan negara. More simply again that which immediately sets the thing in motion. Dengan kata lain lagi yang segera menentukan hal dalam gerakan. So take the
  • 33. two dominos this time of equal weighting, the first is knocked over causing the second also to fall over. Jadi mengambil dua dominos ini waktu sama bobot, yang pertama adalah melalui knocked menyebabkan kedua juga jatuh. This is effectively efficient cause. Hal ini menyebabkan secara efektif efisien. · The final cause is that for the sake of which a thing exists or is done, including both purposeful and instrumental actions and activities. Akhir adalah bahwa untuk kepentingan apapun yang ada atau dilakukan, termasuk kedua sengaja dan tindakan instrumental dan kegiatan. The final cause or telos is the purpose or end that something is supposed to serve, or it is that from which and that to which the change is. Akhir menyebabkan atau telos adalah tujuan akhir atau sesuatu yang digunakan untuk melayani, atau adalah bahwa dari mana dan ke mana perubahan itu. This also covers modern ideas of mental causation involving such psychological causes as volition, need, motivation, or motives, rational, irrational, ethical, all that gives purpose to behavior. Ini juga mencakup ide-ide modern dari hal menyebabkan mental melibatkan sebagai penyebab psikologis seperti kemauan, kebutuhan, motivasi, atau motif, rasional, irasional, etika, yang tujuannya untuk memberikan perilaku. Additionally, things can be causes of one another, causing each other reciprocally, as hard work causes fitness and vice versa, although not in the same way or function, the one is as the beginning of change, the other as the goal. Selain itu, hal ini dapat menyebabkan dari satu sama lain, sehingga satu sama lain begitu, kerja keras sebagai penyebab kebugaran dan sebaliknya, walaupun tidak dengan cara yang sama atau fungsi, yang satu adalah sebagai awal dari perubahan, yang lain sebagai tujuan. (Thus Aristotle first suggested a reciprocal or circular causality as a relation of mutual dependence or influence of cause upon effect). (Oleh karena itu disarankan Aristotel pertama yang timbal atau surat edaran hubungan sebab dan akibat sebagai hubungan yang saling ketergantungan atau pengaruh atas menimbulkan efek). Moreover, Aristotle indicated that the same thing can be the cause of contrary effects; its presence and absence may result in different outcomes. Selain itu, Aristotle menunjukkan bahwa hal yang sama yang dapat menyebabkan efek yang berlawanan; kehadiran dan ketidakhadiran yang dapat menyebabkan hasil yang berbeda. Simply it is the goal or purpose that brings about an event (not necessarily a mental goal). Cukup adalah tujuan atau tujuan yang membawa tentang aktivitas (mental yang belum tentu tujuan). Taking our two dominos, it requires someone to intentionally knock the dominos over as they cannot fall themselves. Mengambil dua dominos, ia memerlukan seseorang untuk sengaja membuat dominos atas karena mereka tidak bisa jatuh sendiri. Aristotle marked two modes of causation: proper (prior) causation and accidental (chance) causation. Aristotel ditandai dari dua hal menyebabkan mode: tepat (sebelumnya) dan hal menyebabkan kebetulan (kemungkinan) hal menyebabkan. All causes, proper and incidental, can be spoken as potential or as actual, particular or generic. Semua penyebab, tepat dan insidentil, dapat digunakan sebagai potensi atau sebenarnya, khusus atau umum. The same language refers to the effects of causes, so that generic effects assigned to generic causes, particular effects to particular causes, operating causes to actual effects. Bahasa yang sama merujuk pada efek dari penyebab, sehingga efek yang ditugaskan untuk umum penyebab umum, khususnya menyebabkan efek tertentu, operasi untuk menyebabkan efek yang sebenarnya. Essentially, causality does not suggest a temporal relation between the cause and the effect. Pada dasarnya, hubungan sebab dan akibat tidak menyarankan sementara hubungan antara penyebab dan efek.